SOCIAL COGNITION AND THEORY OF MIND
The
social world provides yet another domain in which young children are
surpris-ingly competent (Striano & Reid, 2006). For example, infants seem
to have some understanding of other people’s intentions. Specifically, they understand the world they observe in
terms of others’ goals, and not just their movements. In one study, 6-month-old
infants saw an actor reach for a ball that was sitting just to the right of a
teddy bear. (The left–right position of the toys was reversed for half of the
infants tested.) The infant watched this event over and over, until he became
bored with it. At that point, the position of the toys was switched, so now the
teddy bear was on the right. Then the infant was shown one of two test events.
In one, the actor again reached for the ball (although, given the switch in position,
this was the first time the infant had seen a reach toward the left). In the
other condition, the actor again reached for the object on the right (although,
given the switch, this was the first time the infant had seen a reach toward
the teddy bear).
If,
in the initial observation, the infant was focusing on behavior (“reach
right”), then the reach-for-ball test event involves a change, and so will be a
surprise. If, however, the infant was focusing on the goal (“reach for ball”),
then it is the reach for the teddy bear that involves a change, and will be a
surprise. And, in fact, the latter is what the data show: Six-month-olds are
more surprised by the change in goal than by the change in behavior (A. L.
Woodward, 1998; Figure 14.15). Apparently, and contrary to Piaget, they
understand that the object reached for is separate from the reach itself, and
they are sophisticated enough in their perceptions that they understand others’
actions in terms of intended goals (see also Brandone & Wellman, 2009; Luo
& Baillargeon, 2005; Surian, Caldi, & Sperber, 2007; Woodward, 2009).
This
emerging understanding of others’ intentions is important, because it allows
the young child to make sense of, and in many cases predict, how others will
behave. However, understanding intentions is just one aspect of the young
child’s developing theory of mind—the
set of beliefs that someone employs whenever she tries to makesense of her own
behavior or that of others (Leslie, 1992; D. Premack & Woodruff, 1978;
H.
M. Wellman, 1990). The theory of mind also involves preferences—and the young child must come to understand that people
vary in their preferences and that people tend to make choices in accord with
their preferences. Here, too, we see early competence: In one study,
18-month-olds watched as experimenters made “yuck” faces after tasting one food
and smiled broadly after tasting another. The experimenters then made a general
request to these toddlers for food, and the children responded
appropriately—offering the food that the experimenter preferred, even if the
children themselves preferred the other food (Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997;
Rieffe, Terwogt, Koops, Stegge, & Oomen, 2001; for more on the child’s
theory of mind, see A. Gopnik & Meltzoff, 1997).
Yet
another aspect of the theory of mind involves beliefs. Suppose you tell 3-year-old Susie that Johnny wants to
play with his puppy. You also tell her that Johnny thinks the puppy is under
the piano. If Susie is now asked where Johnny will look, she will sensi-bly say
that he will look under the piano (H. M. Wellman & Bartsch, 1988). Like an
adult, a 3-year-old understands that a person’s actions depend not just on what
he sees and desires, but also on what he believes.
Let’s
be careful, though, not to overstate young children’s competence. If asked, for
example, what color an object is, 3-year-olds claim that they can find out just
as easily by touching an object as they can by looking at it (O’Neill,
Astington, & Flavell, 1992). Likewise, 4-year-olds will confidently assert
that they have always known something even if they first learned it from the
experimenter just moments earlier (M. Taylor, Esbensen, & Bennett, 1994).
Another
limitation concerns the child’s understanding of false beliefs. According to
many authors, a 3-year-old does not understand that beliefs can be true or
false and that different people can have different beliefs. Evidence comes from
studies using false-belief tests (Wimmer & Perner, 1983; also Lang &
Perner, 2002). In a typical study of this kind, a child and a teddy bear sit in
front of two boxes, one red and the other green. The experimenter opens the red
box and puts a ball in it. He then opens the green box and shows the child—and
the bear—that this box is empty. The teddy bear is now taken out of the room
(to play for a while), and the experimenter and the child move the ball from
the red box into the green one. Next comes the crucial step. The teddy bear is
brought back into the room, and the child is asked, “Where will the teddy look
for the ball?” Virtually all 3-year-olds and some 4-year-olds will answer, “In
the green box.” If you ask them why, they will answer, “Because that’s where it
is.” It would appear, then, that these children do not really understand the
nature of belief. They seem to assume that their beliefs are inevitably shared
by others, and likewise, they seem not to under-stand that others might have
beliefs that are false (Figure 14.16).
However,
by age 4-1/2 or so, children get the idea that not all knowledge is shared. If
they are asked, “Where will the teddy look for the candy?” they will answer,
“He’ll look in the red box because that’s where he thinks the candy is” (H.
Wellman & Lagattuta, 2000; H. Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001). The
children now seem to have learned that different individuals have different
beliefs, and that one’s beliefs depend on access to the relevant information.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.