Rights and Responsibilities
Although the US Supreme Court has expounded no
national, con-stitutionally based right to treatment, there has been a
substantial amount of activity in this area since Birnbaum published “The Right
to Treatment’’ in 1960. At the time the article was published, it was common
for psychiatric patients to spend decades in hospi-tals, at times
involuntarily, while receiving little treatment or only custodial care. The
article attempted to upgrade the quality of care in hospitals by creating a
hospitalization-treatment quid pro quo. Birnbaum (1965) later criticized state
hospital conditions, declar-ing that “Personally, I should like to state that
as a doctor I often find it repugnant to use the term ‘patient’ to describe persons
in certain mental hospitals’’. He instead argued that “inmate’’ was a better
term if no treatment were given. Birnbaum’s landmark ar-ticles generated
interest in this key area of mental health policy.
Birnbaum’s quid pro quo rationale was endorsed in Rouse v. Cameron (1966) decided by Judge Bazelon of the District of Columbia Circuit Court. Rouse was found not guilty by reason of in-sanity on a misdemeanor charge and was thereafter civilly committed to St Elizabeth’s Hospital. He petitioned for his release based on the argument that he was not receiving treatment. Judge Bazelon ruled that hospitals must make real efforts to improve patients’ conditions and that lack of resources was not an adequate defense. In his decision he wrote, “The hospital need not show that the treatment will cure or improve him but only that there is a bona fide effort to do so’’.
The case of Wyatt
v. Stickney (1972), a class action suit against an Alabama hospital with
poor conditions for patients, led to definitions of humane environment, which
have been incorporated into a patient’s bill of rights in many states. Chief
Judge Johnson wrote for the US District Court, “[Involuntarily committed
patients] unquestionably have a constitutional right to receive such individual
treatment as will give each of them a realistic opportunity to be cured or to
improve his or her mental condition’’. Although this case was not heard by the
US Supreme Court, it did have far-reaching social consequences for
institu-tions in that it prompted scrutiny of the services they provide.
It was not until 1982, in the case of Youngberg v. Romeo (1982), that the
Court held that a person who is involuntarily con-fined has a right to
“minimally adequate training’’. Romeo was a profoundly retarded man who
suffered injuries “on at least 63 occasions … by his own violence and by the
reactions of other residents to him’’ while he was an inpatient at Pennhurst
State Hospital in Pennsylvania. His mother sued, arguing that Romeo’s Eighth
and Fourteenth Amendment rights were being violated. The US Supreme Court
agreed that Romeo had “constitutionally protected liberty interests under the
Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to reasonably safe conditions of
confine-ment, freedom from unreasonable bodily restraints, and such minimally
adequate training as reasonably may be required by these interests’’.
“Minimally adequate training’’ required the ex-ercise of professional judgment,
which was held to be presump-tively valid and to which “courts must show
deference’’.
Most of the right to treatment cases attacked
institutional standards of care, and were based on efforts to expand the scope
of constitutional rights of inpatients. As will be seen below, cur-rent
litigation seeking to establish rights to treatment in the com-munity focuses
largely on the statutory rights afforded by such anti-discrimination statutes
as the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA).
Patients with little or no insight into the nature
of their psychiat-ric illness often refuse treatment. A compelling set of
ethical and legal questions arises when a person’s stated choice (not to
re-ceive treatment) appears to conflict with medical prediction that the
person’s insight and mental status would probably improve with treatment. In
the past, a general assumption that mentally ill patients were, by definition,
incompetent, led society to grant psychiatrists a great deal of autonomy in
selecting and adminis-tering treatments to patients. With the consumer activism
of the 1960s and 1970s and the accompanying development of patients’ rights,
however, psychiatrists and legal authorities have come to see that
involuntarily committed patients are not always glob-ally incompetent, and
efforts to support patients’ rights to refuse treatment have increased.
Although the US Supreme Court has not declared a
federal right to refuse treatment, federal Appeals Courts and most state courts
have found such rights in the federal or state constitutions, citing the due process
clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, within the right to privacy, bodily
integrity, or per-sonal security.
Appelbaum (1988) has described two broad models of
treatment refusal. The “rights-driven’’ model seeks to maximize patient
autonomy. It is based on the principle that competent adults have the right to
reject treatment, even if the rejection of such treatment may result in harm or
even death. States that adopt this model focus on the patient’s competence to
make the decision and often have considerable judicial procedures protecting
patients. The laws of these states typically remove decision-making power from
the psychiatrist and vest it in a guardian or the court. In these states the
guardian or court decides what the patient would want if he or she were
competent (the “substituted judgment’’ standard). The substituted judgment
doctrine requires a challenging deci-sion: it means that the judicial
decision-maker must decide, based not on his or her own values and interests,
or even on what may objectively be in the patient’s best interests, but instead
on what the patient would decide if he or she were competent.
The “treatment-driven’’ model tends to view
treatment as an essential element of commitment to a hospital. States with this
model tend to give psychiatrists more autonomy in making decisions for
patients. Procedural review is done primarily by psychiatrists and is usually
focused on whether the treatment is appropriate to the patients’ conditions. A
series of cases ema-nating from Massachusetts is emblematic of the
rights-driven model. In the matter of Guardianship
of Richard Roe III (1981), the court noted on involuntary psychiatric
medication for psychi-atric outpatients, stating, “If an incompetent individual
refuses antipsychotic drugs, those charged with his protection must seek
judicial determination of substituted judgment’’.
A later Massachusetts case, Rogers v. Commissioner of Mental
Health (1983), applied this rationale to involuntary inpa-tients.
Incompetent patients at Boston State Hospital were being given antipsychotic
medication without the opportunity to give informed consent. The Rogers case
upholds the right of com-mitted mentally ill patients to make treatment
decisions unless they have been adjudicated incompetent by a court. The Rogers
court also affirmed the holding that treatment with antipsychotic medication
constituted extraordinary treatment, and that author-ity to administer such
medication to an incompetent individual required the exercise of the
individual’s substituted judgment. The court outlined six factors that a judge
must assess when de-termining whether a patient should be permitted to refuse
treat-ment: 1) the patient’s previously expressed preference; 2) the patient’s
religious convictions; 3) the impact on family of the patient’s preference; 4)
probable side effects; 5) prognosis with treatment; and 6) prognosis without
treatment. Several cases il-lustrate the treatment-driven model. Rennie v. Klein (1983), de-cided in the
Third Circuit of the US Court of Appeals, held that New Jersey’s procedures for
reviewing the administration of antipsychotics to an unwilling patient were
consistent with due process: the “decision to administer such drugs against a
patient’s will must be based on accepted professional judgment’’. Rather than
have the courts superimpose procedural safeguards, treat-ment-driven model
cases defer to medical judgment. The Rennie decision relied on the US Supreme
Court’s deference to profes-sional judgment in Youngberg v. Romeo (1982).
Although it is generally agreed that patients have
a right to be treated in the least restrictive setting, there are times when a
person’s mental illness is such that he or she must be
hospitalizedinvoluntarily. Each state has different provisions for short-term
emergency commitment. Many states have removed this process from the judicial
setting; some states, however, require a prob-able cause hearing before even an
emergency commitment. The purpose of such a hearing is to determine whether
there is prob-able cause to believe that the person meets the legal criteria
for involuntary hospitalization. If the patient is hospitalized after such a
hearing, it is generally for a short period of time for evalu-ation; if it is
determined that the patient needs longer involuntary hospitalization, then the
statutory procedures for long-term com-mitment must be followed.
In the case of O’Connor
v. Donaldson (1975), the US Supreme Court set a minimum below which states
cannot set their standards for civil commitment. The Court wrote: “The state
cannot constitutionally confine without more, a nondanger-ous, mentally ill
person who is capable of surviving safely by himself or with the help of family
or friends’’. While the Court did not state what it meant by “more’’, most
states now require a finding of dangerousness in addition to mental illness.
In Addington
v. Texas (1979), the US Supreme Court recog-nized the substantial liberty
interest involved in a commitment, and set the minimum standard of proof for
commitment cases as “clear and convincing’’. The court ruled: “The individual’s
lib-erty interest in the outcome of a civil commitment proceeding is of such
weight and gravity, compared with the state’s inter-ests in providing care to
its citizens who are unable, because of emotional disorders, to care for
themselves…that due process requires the State to justify commitment by proof
more substan-tial than mere preponderance of the evidence…. The reasonable- doubt
standard is inappropriate in civil commitment proceedings because, given the
uncertainty of psychiatric diagnosis, it may impose a burden the state cannot
meet and thereby erect an un-reasonable barrier to needed medical treatment’’.
(A few states do interpret their own constitutions to require proof beyond a
reasonable doubt.)
The standards for long-term commitment vary from
state to state, but they all rely on two broad principles of state power. One
is the parens patriae power; the
other, the police power. Parens patriae, translated from Latin as
“father of the country’’, histori-cally referred to the sovereign’s power to
make decisions for the subjects. A more contemporary translation is “state as
parent’’, which refers to the government’s interest in, and responsibility to
act for, individuals who are unable to care for themselves. Parens patriae is used as a rationale for commitment when a person is unable to care for herself or himself
as a result of a mental ill-ness or when he or she poses a danger to self. The
police power stems from the state’s interest in maintaining public safety. The
commitment criterion of “dangerousness to others’’ is derived from the police
power. Over time, the trend in legislation and in court action has been more
toward the dangerousness standard and less toward disability. Under all current
statutes, a finding of mental illness is a prerequisite to commitment Table
6.2.
The notion of dangerousness to others or to self is
a prob-lematical one for psychiatrists, given that prediction of harm is an inexact
science. Complicating the picture is the fact that states also require
different levels of proof that people are dangerous to themselves. Some states
require imminent harm, while oth-ers are more tolerant of general predictions
of future dangerous-ness based on a patient’s pattern of treatment
noncompliance and decompensation.
Finally, many states require a finding that
hospitalization is the least restrictive method to prevent the harm the patient
faces. In Lake
v. Cameron (1966), the District of Columbia Court of Appeals held that a
60-year-old demented homeless woman could not be involuntarily hospitalized if
there were other alter-natives. This case is most famous for the concept of
“least restric-tive alternative’’, as it focused on the place of confinement as
well as the fact of confinement.
The issues underlying the threshold for commitment
are fundamentally social, not psychiatric. They entail a balancing of rights
and liberty interests with needs for treatment and safety. This balance has
historically shifted with changes in the political and social climate, and
continues to be a source of debate in both the legal and mental health fields.
In 1985, the APA developed a Model Law for
Commitment, which generated considerable debate in the profession: “[I]t was
conceived in response to the…‘libertarian model,’ which many mental health
professionals and growing numbers of families be-lieved was unworkable,
unrealistic and inhumane’’ (Stone, 1985). Stone added that “the liberty of psychotic
persons to sleep in the streets of America is hardly a cherished freedom’’ and
advocated for greater discretion for psychiatric commitment as well as greater
resources for treatment once the patient is hospitalized.
Progress in the treatment of severe and chronic
mental illness often depends upon the patient’s compliance with medication and
other treatment regimens in the community. This has been a source of challenge
and frustration for psychiatrists who treat such patients. In recent years
there has been a growth of interest in the possibility that outpatient
commitment may offer a way to ensure that those who most need treatment will in
fact receive it. In principle, an outpatient commitment law allows the same
sort of treatment options as already exist with inpatient commit-ment: a
patient may be deprived of liberty and, if found to be incompetent to make
medication decisions, may be made to take medication against his will. While
inpatient commitment is justi-fied when a patient represents a danger or cannot
care for himself, how does one justify coercing a patient who may be stable,
rela-tively symptom-free and functioning in the community?
Here the legal debate splits into two camps. Those
in fa-vor of outpatient commitment make several arguments: 1) the treatments
are safe and effective; 2) untreated mental illness may increase the likelihood
of violence, homelessness, incarceration and suicide; and, more
controversially, 3) patients with severe mental illness frequently lack
awareness of their condition, and are therefore not really free when ill
(Torrey and Zdanowicz, 2001). Those opposing outpatient commitment counter
that:
better funded and staffed outpatient programs would
provide the kind of outreach which would make coercion unnecessary; 2) the
prospect of coercion may actually drive certain patients away from help; 3)
public safety would not be enhanced by outpatient commitment; and 4) even the
most ill patient is, in the eyes of the law, still competent to refuse treatment
(Allen and Smith, 2001).
At least 41 states permit some form of outpatient
com-mitment, yet the first two randomized trials examining its use (Steadman et al., 2001; Swartz et al., 2001) provided equivocal
evidence of efficacy (Appelbaum, 2001). The actual mechanics of apprehending a
nondangerous person, taking him/her to some facility, and injecting him/her
involuntarily with medication, all because he/she had not followed through on a
treatment plan, has proven difficult both to implement and to tolerate in a
society which still places great value on maintaining its citizens’ liberty
interests. The debate will continue as psychiatrists try to reduce the
aggregate suffering imposed on individuals and society by the effects of
untreated mental illness.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.