Genes and
Evolution
Darwin’s deeply important
conception boils down to three principles. First, there must be variation among
the individuals within a population. Second, certain of the variants must
survive and reproduce at higher rates than others. Third, the traits associated
with this superior survival and reproduction must be passed from parents to
offspring.
There are, to be sure, many
variations between individuals that do not meet these conditions. As we’ve
discussed, not all variations contribute to survival; nor are all of the traits
in parents passed on to their young. But when these three conditions are met,
Darwin argued, the composition of a population will necessarily change from one
gen-eration to the next. And if this process continues for many generations,
the population will evolve.
These basic ideas seem so
straightforward that one of Darwin’s colleagues, Thomas Henry Huxley, reported
feeling “extremely stupid not to have thought of that” on his own. Perhaps
Huxley should have been easier on himself, though, because Darwin needed to get
past two substantial obstacles in his thinking: He didn’t know why organisms
within in a population differed from each other, and he also didn’t know how
traits could be transmitted from one generation to the next. Of course, he did
know that both of these conditions were often met: Plant and animal breeders
had been developing new varieties for years—selectively breeding the biggest,
healthiest cows in the herd to produce the best possible offspring; carefully
crossing different varieties of corn to obtain a new hybrid with certain
desirable qualities. But what was the mechanism? Why were some cows bigger than
others, and why were some traits—but by no means all—passed from one generation
of corn plants to the next?
The answers to these questions,
we now know, hinge in large part on the organism’s genome. Of course,
individuals differ in their phenotypes for many reasons (different experiences,
different exposure to nutrients, and more), but another reason for these
differences is variation in the genotype. And it’s differences in genotype that
are trans-mitted from one generation to the next.
In thinking about these issues,
let’s keep in mind that all the individuals in a species actually have
enormously similar genomes. Indeed, this genome is a large part of what defines the species, and it’s why
members of the species all have roughly the sameanatomy and physiology. But
against this backdrop of uniformity, individuals do vary in their genotype; and
we’ve already noted one of the reasons—the random element that’s involved in
sexual reproduction. Thanks to this random element, each individual inherits a
new combination of alleles, inevitably introducing some variation into the
population.
Another reason for variations in
genotype involves the process of reproducing chro-mosomes. This process is usually accurate, but it isn’t perfect,
and sometimes mutations occur—errors
in replicating the DNA—so that the chromosomes in the father’s sperm or the
mother’s egg are not exact copies of the chromosomes governing the father’s
biol-ogy or the mother’s. Mutations can happen randomly, and most mutations
either have no effect or harm the
organism. But some mutations do confer an advantage for survival and
reproduction—and, in all cases, mutations contribute to the genetic diversity
within a species, which in turn contributes to the phenotypic diversity that is
the raw material for natural selection.
Clearly, then, our knowledge of
genetics fills in some gaps in Darwin’s account— helping us to understand both
the variations within a population and how these vari-ations can be transmitted
to the next generation. This emphasis on genes also allows us to address a
common misunderstanding of how evolution proceeds: Evolution is often described
as “survival of the fittest,” but this phrase is actually misleading because
survival itself is not all that evolution is about. Personal survival does
matter, of course, but only insofar as it enables the organism to reproduce and
pass along its genes to the next generation.
To see the importance of this
emphasis on genes, consider a behav-ior observed in many birds, such as the
piping plover: When a preda-tor approaches the plover’s nest, the mother bird
flies a short distance away from her young, lands, and hops around, dragging
one wing in a way that suggests she’s injured and unable to escape (Figure
2.10). The predator spots this (seemingly) easy target and turns away from the
young, pursuing the apparently injured mother instead. In this way, the mother
can lead the predator away from her chicks; then, once her brood is safe, she
reveals that in fact she is perfectly healthy and flies swiftly away.
This behavior protects the bird’s
young but puts the mother plover at substantial risk. When feigning injury,
she’s highly vulnerable to the approaching predator; she would surely be safer
if she immediately flew to safety. Still, the evolution-ary basis for this
behavior is easy to understand: The mother herself would survive if she
immediately flew to safety, but in that case the predator would probably eat
her chicks. As a result, the mother bird would have fewer offspring to whom she
has passed her genes. Let’s also assume that the plovers’ genome helps to shape
her maternal behav-ior—and, in particular, plays a role in determining whether
the mother plover puts her-self at risk to protect her brood, or abandons the
nest to save her own skin. We can now see that if an individual plover happens
to have genes favoring a self-protective response, she’s more likely to
survive, but less likely to contribute copies of those genes to future
generations. As a result, any genes promoting self-protection would become less
common in the population. Natural selection would therefore end up favoring the
protective mother—or, more accurately, would favor the genes that help shape
this pro-tective behavior—and so this behavior would become the dominant
pattern in the population.
A similar argument applies to
cases in which an organism protects individuals that are not its offspring. For
example, if a Belding’s ground squirrel sees a predator, it gives a cry of
alarm. The cry warns other ground squirrels so that they can scurry to safety.
But, by sounding the alarm, the first ground squirrel gives away its location
and so puts itself in danger. If we focus on individual survival, therefore,
this behavior makes no evolutionary sense. Once again, though, we need to think
in terms of the genes’ survival, not
the individual’s. The other squirrels protected by the alarm call share many of
the first ground squirrel’s genes, and so by protecting these other
individuals, the squirrel protects its genes—including the genes that promoted
this helpful behavior. The genes that favor this behavior will then be more
likely to be passed along to the next generation—and the genes, as always, are
what evolution is about.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.