Beliefs
No
account of the scientific picture of the world and its history would be
complete unless it contained a reminder of the fact, frequently forgotten by
scientists themselves, that this picture does not even claim to be
comprehensive. From the world we actually live in, the world that is given by
our senses, our intuitions of beauty and goodness, our emotions and impulses,
our moods and sentiments, the man of science abstracts a simplified private
universe of things possessing only those qualities which used to be called
"primary." Arbitrarily, because it happens to be convenient, because
his methods do not allow him to deal with the immense complexity of reality, he
selects from the whole of experience only those elements which can be weighed,
measured, numbered, or which lend themselves in any other way to mathematical
treatment. By using this technique of simplification and abstraction, the
scientist has succeeded to an astonishing degree in understanding and
dominating the physical environment. The success was intoxicating and, with an
illogicality which, in the circumstances, was doubtless pardonable, many
scientists and philosophers came to imagine that this useful abstraction from
reality was reality itself. Reality as actually experienced contains intuitions
of value and significance, contains love, beauty, mystical ecstasy, intimations
of godhead. Science did not and still does not possess intellectual instruments
with which to deal with these aspects of reality. Consequently it ignored them
and concentrated its attention upon such aspects of the world as it could deal
with by means of arithmetic, geometry and the various branches of higher
mathematics. Our conviction that the world is meaningless is due in part to the
fact (discussed in a later paragraph) that the philosophy of meaninglessness
lends itself very effectively to furthering the ends of erotic or political
passion; in part to a genuine intellectual error - the error of identifying the
world of science, a world from which all meaning and value has been
deliberately excluded, with ultimate reality. It is worth while to quote in
this context the words with which Hume closes his Enquiry. "If we
take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance;
let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or
number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of
fact or evidence? No. Commit it then to the flames; for it can contain nothing
but sophistry and illusion." Hume mentions only divinity and school
metaphysics; but his argument would apply just as cogently to poetry, music,
painting, sculpture and all ethical and religious teaching. Hamlet contains no
abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number and no experimental reason
concerning evidence; nor does the Hammerklavier Sonata, nor Donatello's David,
nor the Tao Te Ching, nor the Following of Christ. Commit them
therefore to the flames: for they can contain nothing but sophistry and
illusion.
We
are living now, not in the delicious intoxication induced by the early
successes of science, but in a rather grisly morning-after, when it has become apparent
that what triumphant science has done hitherto is to improve the means for
achieving unimproved or actually deteriorated ends. In this condition of
apprehensive sobriety we are able to see that the contents of literature, art,
music - even in some measure of divinity and school metaphysics - are not
sophistry and illusion, but simply those elements of experience which
scientists chose to leave out of account, for the good reason that they had no
intellectual methods for dealing with them. In the arts, in philosophy, in
religion men are trying - doubtless, without complete success - to describe and
explain the non-measurable, purely qualitative aspects of reality. Since the
time of Galileo, scientists have admitted, sometimes explicitly but much more
often by implication, that they are incompetent to discuss such matters. The
scientific picture of the world is what it is because men of science combine
this incompetence with certain special competences. They have no right to claim
that this product of incompetence and specialization is a complete picture of
reality. As a matter of historical fact, however, this claim has constantly
been made. The successive steps in the process of identifying an arbitrary
abstraction from reality with reality itself have been described, very fully
and lucidly, in Burtt's excellent "Metaphysical Foundations of Modern
Science"; and it is therefore unnecessary for me to develop the theme any
further. All that I need add is the fact that, in recent years, many men of
science have come to realize that the scientific picture of the world is a
partial one - the product of their special competence in mathematics and their
special incompetence to deal systematically with aesthetic and moral values,
religious experiences and intuitions of significance. Unhappily, novel ideas
become acceptable to the less intelligent members of society only with a very
considerable time-lag. Sixty or seventy years ago the majority of scientists
believed - and the belief often caused them considerable distress - that the
product of their special incompetence was identical with reality as a whole.
Today this belief has begun to give way, in scientific circles, to a different
and obviously truer conception of the relation between science and total experience.
The masses, on the contrary, have just reached the point where the ancestors of
today's scientists were standing two generations back. They are convinced that
the scientific picture of an arbitrary abstraction from reality is a picture of
reality as a whole and that therefore the world is without meaning or value.
But nobody likes living in such a world. To satisfy their hunger for meaning
and value, they turn to such doctrines as nationalism, fascism and
revolutionary communism. Philosophically and scientifically, these doctrines
are absurd; but for the masses in every community, they have this great merit:
they attribute the meaning and value that have been taken away from the world
as a whole to the particular part of the world in which the believers happen to
be living.
These
last considerations raise an important question, which must now be considered
in some detail. Does the world as a whole possess the value and meaning that we
constantly attribute to certain parts of it (such as human beings and their
works); and, if so, what is the nature of that value and meaning? This is a
question which, a few years ago, I should not even have posed. For, like so
many of my contemporaries, I took it for granted that there was no meaning.
This was partly due to the fact that I shared the common belief that the
scientific picture of an abstraction from reality was a true picture of reality
as a whole; partly also to other, non-intellectual reasons. I had motives for
not wanting the world to have a meaning; consequently assumed that it had none,
and was able without any difficulty to find satisfying reasons for this
assumption.
Most
ignorance is vincible ignorance. We don't know because we don't want to know.
It is our will that decides how and upon what subjects we shall use our
intelligence. Those who detect no meaning in the world generally do so because,
for one reason or another, it suits their books that the world should be
meaningless.
The
behavior of the insane is merely sane behavior, a bit exaggerated and
distorted. The abnormal casts a revealing light upon the normal. Hence the
interest attaching, among other madmen, to the extravagant figure of the
Marquis de Sade. The marquis prided himself upon being a thinker. His books,
indeed, contain more philosophy than pornography. The hungry smut-hound must
plough through long chapters of abstract speculation in order to find the
cruelties and obscenities for which he hungers. De Sade's philosophy was the
philosophy of meaninglessness carried to its logical conclusion. Life was
without significance. Values were illusory and ideals merely the inventions of
cunning priests and kings. Sensations and animal pleasures alone possessed
reality and were alone worth living for. There was no reason why any one should
have the slightest consideration for any one else. For those who found rape and
murder amusing, rape and murder were fully legitimate activities. And so on.
Why
was the Marquis unable to find any value or significance in the world? Was his
intellect more piercing than that of other men? Was he forced by the acuity of
his vision to look through the veils of prejudice and superstition to the
hideous reality behind them? We may doubt it. The real reason why the Marquis
could see no meaning or value in the world is to be found in those descriptions
of fornications, sodomies and tortures which alternate with the philosophizings
of Justine and Juliette. In the ordinary circumstances of life,
the Marquis was not particularly cruel; indeed, he is said to have got into
serious trouble during the Terror for his leniency toward those suspected of
anti-revolutionary sentiments. His was a strictly sexual perversion. It was for
flogging actresses, sticking pen-knives into shop girls, feeding prostitutes on
sugar-plums impregnated with cantharides, that he got into trouble with the
police. His philosophical disquisitions, which, like the pornographic
day-dreams, were mostly written in prisons and asylums, were the theoretical
justification of his erotic practices. Similarly his politics were dictated by
the desire to avenge himself on those members of his family and his class who
had, as he thought, unjustly persecuted him. He was enthusiastically a
revolutionary - at any rate in theory; for, as we have seen, he was too gentle in
practice to satisfy his fellow Jacobins. His books are of permanent interest
and value because they contain a kind of reductio ad absurdum of
revolutionary theory. Sade is not afraid to be a revolutionary to the bitter
end. Not content with denying the particular system of values embodied in the ancien
régime,
he proceeds
to deny the existence of any values, any idealism, any binding moral
imperatives whatsoever. He preaches violent revolution not only in the field of
politics and economics, but (logical with the appalling logicality of the
maniac) also on that of personal relations, including the most intimate of all,
the relations between lovers. And, after all, why not? If it is legitimate to
torment and kill in one set of circumstances, it must be equally legitimate to
torment and kill in all other circumstances. De Sade is the one completely
consistent and thorough-going revolutionary of history.
If I
have lingered so long over a maniac, it is because his madness illuminates the
dark places of normal behavior. No philosophy is completely disinterested. The
pure love of truth is always mingled to some extent with the need, consciously
or unconsciously felt by even the noblest and the most intelligent
philosophers, to justify a given form of personal or social behavior, to
rationalize the traditional prejudices of a given class or community. The
philosopher who finds meaning in the world is concerned, not only to elucidate
that meaning, but also to prove that it is most clearly expressed in some
established religion, some accepted code of morals. The philosopher who finds
no meaning in the world is not concerned exclusively with a problem in pure
metaphysics. He is also concerned to prove that there is no valid reason why he
personally should not do as he wants to do, or why his friends should not seize
political power and govern in the way that they find most advantageous to
themselves. The voluntary, as opposed to the intellectual, reasons for holding
the doctrines of materialism, for example, may be predominantly erotic, as they
were in the case of Lamettrie (see his lyrical account of the pleasures of the
bed in La Volupté and at the end of L'Homme Machine), or predominantly political,
as they were in the case of Karl Marx. The desire to justify a particular form
of political organization and, in some cases, of a personal will to power has
played an equally large part in the formulation of philosophies postulating the
existence of a meaning in the world. Christian philosophers have found no
difficulty in justifying imperialism, war, the capitalistic system, the use of
torture, the censorship of the press, and ecclesiastical tyrannies of every
sort from the tyranny of Rome to the tyrannies of Geneva and New England. In
all these cases they have shown that the meaning of the world was such as to be
compatible with, or actually most completely expressed by, the iniquities I
have mentioned above - iniquities which happened, of course, to serve the
personal or sectarian interests of the philosophers concerned. In due course,
there arose philosophers who denied not only the right of these Christian
special pleaders to justify iniquity by an appeal to the meaning of the world,
but even their right to find any such meaning whatsoever. In the circumstances,
the fact was not surprising. One unscrupulous distortion of the truth tends to
beget other and opposite distortions. Passions may be satisfied in the process;
but the disinterested love of knowledge suffers eclipse.
For
myself as, no doubt, for most of my contemporaries, the philosophy of
meaninglessness was essentially an instrument of liberation. The liberation we
desired was simultaneously liberation from a certain political and economic
system and liberation from a certain system of morality. We objected to the
morality because it interfered with our sexual freedom; we objected to the
political and economic system because it was unjust. The supporters of these
systems claimed that in some way they embodied the meaning (a Christian
meaning, they insisted) of the world. There was one admirably simple method of
confuting these people and at the same time justifying ourselves in our
political and erotic revolt: we could deny that the world had any meaning
whatsoever. Similar tactics had been adopted during the eighteenth century and
for the same reasons. From the popular novelists of the period, such as Crébillon and Andréa de Nerciat, we learn that the chief reason for being
"philosophical" was that one might be free from prejudices - above
all prejudices of a sexual nature. More serious writers associated political
with sexual prejudice and recommended philosophy (in practice, the philosophy
of meaninglessness) as a preparation for social reform or revolution. The early
nineteenth century witnessed a reaction toward meaningful philosophy of a kind
that could, unhappily, be used to justify political reaction. The men of the
new Enlightenment, which occurred in the middle years of the nineteenth
century, once again used meaninglessness as a weapon against the reactionaries.
The Victorian passion for respectability was, however, so great that, during
the period when they were formulated, neither Positivism nor Darwinism was used
as a justification for sexual indulgence. After the War the philosophy of
meaninglessness came once more triumphantly into fashion. As in the days of
Lamettrie and his successors the desire to justify a certain sexual looseness
played a part in the popularization of meaninglessness at least as important as
that played by the desire for liberation from an unjust and inefficient form of
social organization. By the end of the twenties a reaction had begun to set in -
away from the easy-going philosophy of general meaninglessness toward the hard,
ferocious theologies of nationalistic and revolutionary idolatry. Meaning was
reintroduced into the world, but only in patches. The universe as a whole still
remained meaningless, but certain of its parts, such as the nation, the state,
the class, the party, were endowed with significance and the highest value. The
general acceptance of a doctrine that denies meaning and value to the world as
a whole, while assigning them in a supreme degree to certain arbitrarily
selected parts of the totality, can have only evil and disastrous results.
"All that we are (and consequently all that we do) is the result of what
we have thought." We have thought of ourselves as members of supremely
meaningful and valuable communities - deified nations, divine classes and what
not - existing within a meaningless universe. And because we have thought like
this, rearmament is in full swing, economic nationalism becomes ever more
intense, the battle of rival propagandas grows ever fiercer, and general war
becomes increasingly more probable.
It
was the manifestly poisonous nature of the fruits that forced me to reconsider
the philosophical tree on which they had grown. It is certainly hard, perhaps
impossible, to demonstrate any necessary connection between truth and practical
goodness. Indeed it was fashionable during the Enlightenment of the middle
nineteenth century to speak of the need for supplying the masses with
"vital lies" calculated to make those who accepted them not only
happy, but well behaved. The truth - which was that there was no meaning or
value in the world - should be revealed only to the few who were strong enough
to stomach it. Now, it may be, of course, that the nature of things has fixed a
great gulf between truth about the world on the one hand and practical goodness
on the other. Meanwhile, however, the nature of things seems to have so
constituted the human mind that it is extremely reluctant to accept such a
conclusion, except under the pressure of desire or self-interest. Furthermore
those who, to be liberated from political or sexual restraint, accept the doctrine
of absolute meaninglessness tend in a short time to become so much dissatisfied
with their philosophy (in spite of the services it renders) that they will
exchange it for any dogma, however manifestly nonsensical, which restores
meaning if only to a part of the universe. Some people, it is true, can live
contentedly with a philosophy of meaninglessness for a very long time. But in
most cases it will be found that these people possess some talent or
accomplishment that permits them to live a life which, to a limited extent, is
profoundly meaningful and valuable. Thus an artist, or a man of science can
profess a philosophy of general meaninglessness and yet lead a perfectly
contented life. The reason for this must be sought in the fact that artistic
creation and scientific research are absorbingly delightful occupations,
possessing, moreover, a certain special significance in virtue of their
relation to truth and beauty. Nevertheless, artistic creation and scientific
research may be, and constantly are, used as devices for escaping from the
responsibilities of life. They are proclaimed to be ends absolutely good in
themselves - ends so admirable that those who pursue them are excused from
bothering about anything else. This is particularly true of contemporary
science. The mass of accumulated knowledge is so great that it is now
impossible for any individual to have a thorough grasp of more than one small
field of study. Meanwhile, no attempt is made to produce a comprehensive
synthesis of the general results of scientific research. Our universities
possess no chair of synthesis. All endowments, moreover, go to special subjects
- and almost always to subjects which have no need of further endowment, such
as physics, chemistry and mechanics. In our institutions of higher learning
about ten times as much is spent on the natural sciences as on the sciences of
man. All our efforts are directed, as usual, to producing improved means to
unimproved ends. Meanwhile intensive specialization tends to reduce each branch
of science to a condition almost approaching meaninglessness. There are many
men of science who are actually proud of this state of things. Specialized
meaninglessness has come to be regarded, in certain circles, as a kind of hall
mark of true science. Those who attempt to relate the small particular results
of specialization with human life as a whole and its relation to the universe
at large are accused of being bad scientists, charlatans, self-advertisers. The
people who make such accusations do so, of course, because they do not wish to
take any responsibility for anything, but merely to retire to their cloistered
laboratories, and there amuse themselves by performing delightfully interesting
researches. Science and art are only too often a superior kind of dope,
possessing this advantage over booze and morphia: that they can be indulged in
with a good conscience and with the conviction that, in the process of
indulging, one is leading the "higher life." Up to a point, of
course, this is true. The life of the scientist or the artist is a higher life.
Unfortunately, when led in an irresponsible, one-sided way, the higher life is
probably more harmful for the individual than the lower life of the average
sensual man and certainly, in the case of the scientist, much worse for society
at large. . .
We
are now at the point at which we discover that an obviously untrue philosophy
of life leads in practice to disastrous results; the point where we realize the
necessity of seeking an alternative philosophy that shall be true and therefore
fruitful of good. A critical consideration of the classical arguments in favor
of theism would reveal that some carry no conviction whatever, while the rest
can only raise a presumption in favor of the theory that the world possesses
some integrating principle that gives it significance and value. There is
probably no argument by which the case for theism, or for deism, or for
pantheism in either its pancosmic or acosmic form, can be convincingly proved.
The most that "abstract reasoning" (to use Hume's phrase) can do is
to create a presumption in favor of one or other hypothesis; and this
presumption can be increased by means of "experimental reasoning
concerning matter of fact or evidence." Final conviction can only come to
those who make an act of faith. The idea is one which most of us find very
distressing. But it may be doubted whether this particular act of faith is
intrinsically more difficult than those which we have to make, for example,
every tune we frame a scientific hypothesis, every time that, from the
consideration of a few phenomena, we draw inference concerning all phenomena,
past, present and future. On very little evidence, but with no qualms of
intellectual conscience, we assume that our craving for explanation has a real
object in an explicable universe, that the aesthetic satisfaction we derive
from certain arguments is a sign that they are true, that the laws of thought
are also laws of things. There seems to be no reason why, having swallowed this
camel, we should not swallow another, no larger really than the first. Once
recognized, the reasons why we strain at the second camel cease to exist and we
become free to consider on their merits the evidence and arguments that would
reasonably justify us in making the final act of faith and assuming the truth
of a hypothesis that we are unable fully to demonstrate.
"Abstract
reasoning" must now give place to "experimental reasoning concerning
matter of fact or evidence." Natural science, as we have seen, deals only
with those aspects of reality that are amenable to mathematical treatment. The
rest it merely ignores. But some of the experiences thus ignored by natural
science - aesthetic experiences, for example, and religious experiences - throw
much light upon the present problem. It is with the fact of such experiences
and the evidence they furnish concerning the nature of the world that we have
now to concern ourselves.
To
discuss the nature and significance of aesthetic experience would take too
long. It is enough, in this place, merely to suggest that the best works of
literary, plastic and musical art give us more than mere pleasure; they furnish
us with information about the nature of the world. The Sanctus in
Beethoven's Mass in D, Seurat's Grande Jatte, Macbeth - works such as
these tell us, by strange but certain implication, something significant about
the ultimate reality behind appearances. Even from the perfection of minor
masterpieces - certain sonnets of Mallarmé, for instance, certain Chinese
ceramics - we can derive illuminating hints about the "something far more
deeply interfused," about "the peace of God that passeth all
understanding." But the subject of art is enormous and obscure, and my
space is limited, I shall therefore confine myself to a discussion of certain
religious experiences which bear more directly upon the present problem than do
our experiences as creators and appreciators of art.
Meditation,
in Babbitt's words, is a device for producing a "super-rational
concentration of the will." But meditation is more than a method of
self-education; it has also been used, in every part of the world and from the
remotest periods, as a method for acquiring knowledge about the essential
nature of things, a method for establishing communion between the soul and the
integrating principle of the universe. Meditation, in other words, is the
technique of mysticism. Properly practiced, with due preparation, physical,
mental and moral, meditation may result in a state of what has been called
"transcendental consciousness" - the direct intuition of, and union
with, an ultimate spiritual reality that is perceived as simultaneously beyond
the self and in some way within it. ("God in the depths of us," says
Ruysbroeck, "receives God who comes to us; it is God contemplating
God.") Non-mystics have denied the validity of the mystical experience,
describing it as merely subjective and illusory. But it should be remembered
that to those who have never actually had it, any direct intuition must seem
subjective and illusory. It is impossible for the deaf to form any idea of the
nature or significance of music. Nor is physical disability the only obstacle
in the way of musical understanding. An Indian, for example, finds European
orchestral music intolerably noisy, complicated, over-intellectual, inhuman. It
seems incredible to him that any one should be able to perceive beauty and
meaning, to recognize an expression of the deepest and subtlest emotions in
this elaborate cacophony. And yet, if he has patience and listens to enough of
it, he will come at last to realize, not only theoretically but also by direct,
immediate intuition, that this music possesses all the qualities which
Europeans claim for it. Of the significant and pleasurable experiences of life
only the simplest are open indiscriminately to all. The rest cannot be had
except by those who have undergone a suitable training. One must be trained
even to enjoy the pleasures of alcohol and tobacco; first whiskies seem
revolting, first pipes turn even the strongest of boyish stomachs. Similarly
first Shakespeare sonnets seem meaningless; first Bach fugues, a bore; first
differential equations, sheer torture. But training changes the nature of our
spiritual experiences. In due course, contact with an obscurely beautiful poem,
an elaborate piece of counterpoint or of mathematical reasoning, causes us to
feel direct intuitions of beauty and significance. It is the same in the moral
world. A man who has trained himself in goodness comes to have certain direct
intuitions about character, about the relations between human beings, about his
own position in the world - intuitions that are quite different from the
intuitions of the average sensual man. Knowledge is always a function of being.
What we perceive and understand depends upon what we are; and what we are
depends partly on circumstances, partly, and more profoundly, on the nature of
the efforts we have made to realize our ideal and the nature of the ideal we
have tried to realize. The fact that knowing depends upon being leads, of
course, to an immense amount of misunderstanding. The meaning of words, for
example, changes profoundly according to the character and experiences of the
user. Thus, to the saint, words like "love," "charity,"
"compassion" mean something quite different from what they mean to
the ordinary man. Again, to the ordinary man, Spinoza's statement that
"blessedness is not the reward of virtue, but is virtue itself" seems
simply untrue. Being virtuous is, for him, a most tedious and distressing
process. But it is clear that to some one who has trained himself in goodness,
virtue really is blessedness, while the life of the ordinary man, with its
petty vices and its long spells of animal thoughtlessness and insentience,
seems a real torture. In view of the fact that knowing is conditioned by being
and that being can be profoundly modified by training, we are justified in
ignoring most of the arguments by which non-mystics have sought to discredit
the experience of mystics. The being of a color-blind man is such that he is
not competent to pass judgment on a painting. The color-blind man cannot be
educated into seeing colors, and in this respect he is different from the
Indian musician, who begins by finding European symphonies merely deafening and
bewildering, but can be trained, if he so desires, to perceive the beauties of
this kind of music. Similarly, the being of a non-mystical person is such that
he cannot understand the nature of the mystic's intuitions. Like the Indian
musician, however, he is at liberty, if he so chooses, to have some kind of
direct experience of what at present he does not understand. This training is
one which he will certainly find extremely tedious; for it involves, at first,
the leading of a life of constant awareness and unremitting moral effort;
second, steady practice in the technique of meditation, which is probably about
as difficult as the technique of violin playing. But, however tedious, the
training can be undertaken by any one who wishes to do so. Those who have not
undertaken the training can have no knowledge of the kind of experiences open
to those who have undertaken it and are as little justified in denying the
validity of those direct intuitions of an ultimate spiritual reality, at once
transcendent and immanent, as were the Pisan professors who denied, on a
priori grounds, the validity of Galileo's direct intuition (made possible
by the telescope) of the fact that Jupiter has several moons. . .
Systematic
training in recollection and meditation makes possible the mystical experience,
which is a direct intuition of ultimate reality. At all times and in every part
of the world, mystics of the first order have always agreed that this ultimate
reality, apprehended in the process of meditation, is essentially impersonal.
This direct intuition of an impersonal spiritual reality, underlying all being,
is in accord with the findings of the majority of the world's philosophers.
"There
is," writes Professor Whitehead, in Religion in the Making, "a
large concurrence in the negative doctrine that the religious experience does
not include any direct intuition of a definite person, or individual. . . The
evidence for the assertion of a general, though not universal, concurrence in
the doctrine of no direct vision of a personal God, can only be found by a
consideration of the religious thought of the civilized world. . . Throughout
India and China, religious thought, so far as it has been interpreted in
precise form, disclaims the intuition of ultimate personality substantial to the
universe. This is true of Confucian philosophy, Buddhist philosophy and Hindu
philosophy. There may be personal embodiments, but the substratum is
impersonal. Christian theology has also, in the main, adopted the position that
there is no direct intuition of such a personal substratum for the world. It
maintains the doctrine of a personal God as a truth, but holds that our belief
in it is based upon inference." There seems, however, to be no cogent
reason why, from the existing evidence, we should draw such an inference.
Moreover, the practical results of drawing such an inference are good only up
to a point; beyond that point they are very often extremely bad.
We
are now in a position to draw a few tentative and fragmentary conclusions about
the nature of the world and our relation to it and to one another. To the
casual observer, the world seems to be made up of great numbers of independent
existents, some of which possess life and some consciousness. From very early
times philosophers suspected that this common-sense view was in part at least,
illusory. More recently investigators, trained in the discipline of
mathematical physics and equipped with instruments of precision, have made
observations from which it could be inferred that all the apparently independent
existents in the world were built up of a limited number of patterns of
identical units of energy. An ultimate physical identity underlies the apparent
physical diversity of the world. Moreover, all apparently independent existents
are in fact interdependent. Meanwhile the mystics had shown that investigators,
trained in the discipline of recollection and meditation, could obtain direct
experience of a spiritual unity underlying the apparent diversity of
independent consciousness. They made it clear that what seemed to be the
ultimate fact of personality was in reality not an ultimate fact and that it
was possible for individuals to transcend the limitations of personality and to
merge their private consciousness into a greater, impersonal consciousness
underlying the personal mind. . .
The
physical world of our daily experience is a private universe quarried out of a
total reality which the physicists infer to be far greater than it. This
private universe is different, not only from the real world, whose existence we
are able to infer, even though we cannot directly apprehend it, but also from
the private universe inhabited by other animals - universes which we can never
penetrate, but concerning whose nature we can, as Von Uexkull has done, make interesting
speculative guesses. Each type of living creature inhabits a universe whose
nature is determined and whose boundaries are imposed by the special
inadequacies of its sense organs and its intelligence. In man, intelligence has
been so far developed that he is able to infer the existence and even, to some
extent, the nature of the real world outside his private universe. The nature
of the sense organs and intelligence of living beings is imposed by biological
necessity or convenience. The instruments of knowledge are good enough to
enable their owners to survive. Less inadequate instruments of knowledge might
not only lead to no biological advantage but might actually constitute a
biological handicap. Individual human beings have been able to transcend the
limitations of man's private universe only to the extent that they are relieved
from biological pressure. An individual is relieved from biological pressure in
two ways: from without, thanks to the efforts of others, and from within,
thanks to his own efforts. If he is to transcend the limitations of man's
private universe he must be a member of a community which gives him protection
against the inclemencies of the environment and makes it easy for him to supply
his physical wants. But this is not enough. He must also train himself in the
art of being dispassionate and disinterested, must cultivate intellectual
curiosity for its own sake and not for what he, as an animal, can get out of
it.
The
modern conception of man's intellectual relationship to the universe was
anticipated by the Buddhist doctrine that desire is the source of illusion. To
the extent that it has overcome desire, a mind is free from illusion. This is
true not only of the man of science, but also of the artist and the
philosopher. Only the disinterested mind can transcend common-sense and pass
beyond the boundaries of animal or average-sensual human life. The mystic
exhibits disinterestedness in the highest degree possible to human beings and
is therefore able to transcend ordinary limitations more completely than the
man of science, the artist or the philosopher. That which he discovers beyond
the frontiers of the average sensual man's universe is a spiritual reality
underlying and uniting all apparently separate existents - a reality with which
he can merge himself and from which he can draw moral and even physical powers
which, by ordinary standards, can only be described as super-normal.
The
ultimate reality discoverable by those who choose to modify their being, so
that they can have direct knowledge of it, is not, as we have seen, a
personality. Since it is not personal, it is illegitimate to attribute to it
ethical qualities. "God is not good," said Eckhart. "I am
good." Goodness is the means by which men and women can overcome the
illusion of being completely independent existents and can raise themselves to
a level of being upon which it becomes possible, by recollection and
meditation, to realize the fact of their oneness with ultimate reality, to know
and in some measure actually associate themselves with it. The ultimate reality
is "the peace of God which passeth all understanding"; goodness is
the way by which it can be approached. "Finite beings," in the words
of Royce, "are always such as they are in virtue of an inattention which
at present blinds them to their actual relations to God and to one
another." That inattention is the fruit, in Buddhist language, of desire.
We fail to attend to our true relations with ultimate reality and, through
ultimate reality, with our fellow beings, because we prefer to attend to our
animal nature and to the business of getting on in the world. That we can never
completely ignore the animal in us or its biological needs is obvious. Our
separateness is not wholly an illusion. The element of specificity in things is
a brute fact of experience. Diversity cannot be reduced to complete identity
even in scientific and philosophical theory, still less in life which is lived
with bodies, that is to say, with particular patternings of the ultimately identical
units of energy. It is impossible in the nature of things, that no attention
should be given to the animal in us; but in the circumstances of civilized
life, it is certainly unnecessary to give all or most of our attention to it.
Goodness is the method by which we divert our attention from this singularly
wearisome topic of our animality and our individual separateness. Recollection
and meditation assist goodness in two ways: by producing, in Babbitt's words,
"a supra-rational concentration of will," and by making it possible
for the mind to realize, not only theoretically, but also by direct intuition,
that the private universe of the average sensual man is not identical with the
universe as a whole. Conversely, of course, goodness aids meditation by giving
detachment from animality and so making it possible for the mind to pay
attention to its actual relationship with ultimate reality and to other
individuals. Goodness, meditation, the mystical experience and the ultimate
impersonal reality discovered in mystical experience are organically related.
This fact disposes of the fears expressed by Dr. Albert Schweitzer in his
recent book on Indian thought. Mysticism, he contends, is the correct world
view; but, though correct, it is unsatisfactory in ethical content. The
ultimate reality of the world is not moral ("God is not good") and
the mystic who unites himself with ultimate reality is uniting himself with a
non-moral being, therefore is not himself moral. But this is mere verbalism and
ignores the actual facts of experience. It is impossible for the mystic to pay
attention to his real relation to God and to his fellows, unless he has
previously detached his attention from his animal nature and the business of
being socially successful. But he cannot detach his attention from these things
except by the consistent and conscious practice of the highest morality. God is
not good; but if I want to have even the smallest knowledge of God, I must be
good at least in some slight measure; and if I want as full a knowledge of God
as it is possible for human beings to have, I must be as good as it is possible
for human beings to be. Virtue is the essential preliminary to the mystical
experience. And this is not all. There is not even any theoretical incompatibility
between an ultimate reality, which is impersonal and therefore not moral, and
the existence of a moral order on the human level. Scientific investigation has
shown that the world is a diversity underlain by an identity of physical
substance; the mystical experience testifies to the existence of a spiritual
unity underlying the diversity of separate consciousnesses. Concerning the
relation between the underlying physical unity and the underlying spiritual
unity it is hard to express an opinion. Nor is it necessary, in the present
context, that we should express one. For our present purposes the important
fact is that it is possible to detect a physical and a spiritual unity
underlying the independent existents (to some extent merely apparent, to some
extent real, at any rate for beings on our plane of existence), of which our
commonsense universe is composed. Now, it is a fact of experience that we can
either emphasize our separateness from other beings and the ultimate reality of
the world or emphasize our oneness with them and it. To some extent at least,
our will is free in this matter. Human beings are creatures who, in so far as
they are animals and persons tend to regard themselves as independent
existents, connected at most by purely biological ties, but who, in so far as
they rise above animality and personality, are able to perceive that they are
interrelated parts of physical and spiritual wholes incomparably greater than
themselves. For such beings the fundamental moral commandment is: You shall realize
your unity with all being. But men cannot realize their unity with others and
with ultimate reality unless they practice the virtue of love and
understanding. Love, compassion and understanding or intelligence - these are
the primary virtues in the ethical system, the virtues organically correlated
with what may be called the scientific-mystical conception of the world.
Ultimate reality is impersonal and non-ethical; but if we would realize our
true relations with ultimate reality and our fellow beings, we must practice
morality and (since no personality can learn to transcend itself unless it is
reasonably free from external compulsion) respect the personality of others.
Belief in a personal, moral God has led only too frequently to theoretical dogmatism
and practical intolerance - to a consistent refusal to respect personality and
to the commission in the name of the divinely moral person of every kind of
iniquity.
"The
fact of the instability of evil," in Professor Whitehead's words, "is
the moral order of the world." Evil is that which makes for separateness;
and that which makes for separateness is self-destructive. This
self-destruction of evil may be sudden and violent, as when murderous hatred
results in a conflict that leads to the death of the hater; it may be gradual,
as when a degenerative process results in impotence or extinction; or it may be
reformative, as when a long course of evil-doing results in all concerned
becoming so sick of destruction and degeneration that they decide to change
their ways, thus transforming evil into good.
The
evolutionary history of life clearly illustrates the instability of evil in the
sense in which it has been defined above. Biological specialization may be
regarded as a tendency on the part of a species to insist on its separateness;
and the result of specialization, as we have seen, is either negatively
disastrous, in the sense that it precludes the possibility of further
biological progress, or positively disastrous, in the sense that it leads to
the extinction of the species. In the same way intraspecific competition may be
regarded as the expression of a tendency on the part of related individuals to
insist on their separateness and independence; the effects of intraspecific
competition are, as we have seen, almost wholly bad. Conversely, the qualities
which have led to biological progress are the qualities which make it possible
for individual beings to escape from their separateness - intelligence and the
tendency to co-operate. Love and understanding are valuable even on the
biological level. Hatred, unawareness, stupidity and all that makes for
increase of separateness are the qualities that, as a matter of historical
fact, have led either to the extinction of a species, or to its becoming a
living fossil, incapable of making further biological progress.
(From "Beliefs," Ends and Means)
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.