Heinz Kohut: Self-psychology
Freud and his followers tried to understand
psychological life in terms of biology. Their ideal was scientific objectivity.
They be-lieved the analyst’s human tendency to identify with the subjects of
study impeded objectivity. In contrast, Kohut viewed empathic comprehension as
the fundamental mode of psychoanalytic in-vestigation. It is the knowledge of
the other’s experience, what it is like to be in that person’s shoes. Empathy
is the understand-ing of another’s complex psychological experience as whole.
Using this empathic method, Kohut attempted to create an “experience-near”
psychology, explaining psychological events in terms of meanings and motives
comprehensible from ordinary experience. He contrasted this to Freudian
metapsychology with its postulated experience-distant forces, energies and
structures.
The concept of bipolar
self (Figure 18.3) refers to Kohut’s metaphorical description of the self
as having two poles, one of ideals and ambitions, the other a sense of the
grandiose self. The former involves the sense of being vigorous and coherent
because one is associated with what is good and powerful, for example, that an
adult might have when working in accord with professional ideals. The grandiose
pole of the self consists in the sense of being personally valuable and
appreciated, as a child may feel by virtue of the glowing enthusiasm of
parents.
Kohut’s singular contribution was the idea of the self-object. Clinical observations led
him to believe, like of ob-ject relations theorists, that the self could
survive and prosper only in the context of experience with others. These
experiences Kohut called self-objects, that is, objects (in the psychoanalytic
sense of intrapsychic representation of other people) that are necessary for
the well-being of the self. Kohut was speaking of intrapsychic experiences, not
interpersonal relations. Intrapsy-chic experience may be contingent on
interpersonal events. For example, the sense that one is appreciatively
responded to usu-ally requires some sort of active response from another
person, but how that person’s actions are experienced depends on many factors
besides the actions themselves.
Kohut (1971) described two main types of
self-object. Idealized self-objects embody
what is admirable, strong and vigorous.
The self feels alive and coherent by virtue of proxim-ity to the idealized
self-object. The youngster who feels like “a chip off the old block”, the
student who is enlivened in the pres-ence of a brilliant teacher, and the
religious person who feels safe in God’s presence have idealized self-object
experiences. Mirroring self-objects contribute
to the sense through their support
of the grandiose pole of the self. Kohut described three major types of
mirroring self-object:
· In merger, the self is maintained through
the sense that the person and self-object form a unity that is powerful and
alive in a way the person could not be by himself or herself. The sense of
merger can be found in the feeling that “we” do some-thing. Outside the
analytical situation, it is commonly seen in athletic, professional, and
military activities.
· Alter ego (or twinship) self-object induces a sense of personal coherence by virtue of having a partner who is like oneself.
· The mirroring self-object proper supports
the sense of per-sonal value and coherence through its accurate, valuing
ap-preciation of the person. The person who feels valuable and whole when a
parent’s or friend’s eyes light up as she or he comes into a room or who feels
similarly in response to au-thentic praise of accomplishment is experiencing
such a mir-roring self-object.
Self-objects remain essential throughout life.
Contrary to psychoanalytic theories that characterize maturity in terms of
au-tonomy, self-psychology views mature people as ordinarily depend-ent on
others for appreciation, comradeship, meaning and solace. The nature of the
people and institutions that embody self-objects changes with maturation. They
become more numerous and more complex, often serving many psychological functions
beyond their self-object function. It refers to the total experience of people
and institutions that sustain and support the development of the self.
The study
of self-psychology began with the realization that many symptoms of
psychological distress could be understood as arising from disorders of the
self. These include symptoms in-volving direct experiences of an endangered,
enfeebled, or frag-mented self, and symptoms arising from unsatisfactory
attempts to protect an endangered self. In practice, these symptoms may appear
in the same patient, but for expository purposes, separat-ing them is useful.
Sometimes the symptoms of self-pathology are acute (Figure 18.4), but more
often they are chronic states whose intensity varies as the self is felt to be
more or less in danger.
Symptoms
that directly express the enfeeblement or frag-mentation of the self include
certain depressive states, traumatic states, hypochondriasis, some forms of
rage, called narcissistic rage, and direct experiences of profound
disorganization.
A common
response to feeling the self-endangered is rage (Kohut, 1972). Narcissistic
rage is a major public health prob-lem. The most common cause of violence and
homicide is the rage engendered when people feel “disrespected”. Spousal
mur-ders most commonly result when an already demoralized person is confronted
by apparently trivial inconsiderate behavior and responds with murderous rage.
Communal chronic narcissistic rage may be a major factor in world history when
maintaining group dignity or seeking compensation for past inequities may lead
to hatred and destructiveness lasting for centuries. Narcis-sistic rage varies
from the momentary fury to lifelong states. Like many activities in the service
of the self, narcissistic rage is often rationalized. Perpetrators often
describe violence as necessary to achieve a goal but closer examination usually
shows that vio-lence does little to effect its supposed aim. Physical child
abuse, often a manifestation of narcissistic rage resulting from a sense of
inadequacy in caring for children, is commonly rationalized as “educating” the
youngster. Narcissistic rage often joins other psychological action designed to
invigorate the self.
States
involving the direct experience of fragmentation, in which patients cannot
organize experience or recognize their coherent wishes, are overwhelmingly
distressing. Any solution to this state, including the psychotic reorganization
of experience, feels better. Indeed, such states are most commonly seen briefly
with the onset of overt psychosis. Patients commonly describe this state as
“going crazy” and may attempt desperately to hang on to some organizing
principle. These states are psychiatric emergencies because many patients
report that death is prefer-able to the continuation of the intense anxiety
they experience. Many other symptoms are understandable as attempts to repair
an impaired or endangered self. These include relations with oth-ers designed
to achieve urgently needed self-object experiences and activities designed to
soothe or stimulate the self.
When
self-object functions become unavailable to such an extent that the person
cannot provide for himself or herself these functions based upon personal
abilities and memories al-ready available, a psychological emergency ensues. In
this cir-cumstance, the person uses less broadly adaptive means to try to
compensate for the missing but needed psychological functions. Pathological
functioning is manifested either in direct expression of a distressed self or
as problematic compensatory activities.
Intersubjectivity
in psychoanalysis refers to the dynamic in-terplay between the analyst’s and
the patient’s subjective expe-riences in the clinical situation. To some
extent, all schools of psychoanalysis agree on the significance of
intersubjectivity in psychoanalytic work. Intersubjectivity embodies the notion
that the very formation of the therapeutic process is derived from an
inextricably intertwined mixture of the clinical participants’ subjective
reactions to one another. Knowledge of the patient’s psychology is considered
contextual and idiosyncratic to the par-ticular clinical interaction. This
interaction nexus is considered the primary force of the psychoanalytic
treatment process.
The
intersubjective position is that mental phenomena cannot be sufficiently
understood if approached as an entity that exists within the patient’s mind, conceptually
isolated from the social matrix from which it emerges. Intersubjectiv-ists see
the analyst and the patient together constructing the clinical data from the
interaction of both members’ particular psychic qualities and subjective
realities. The analyst’s per-ceptions of the patient’s psychology are always
shaped by the analyst’s subjectivity. Conversely, the patient’s psychology is
not conceptualized as something discoverable by the external, unbiased observer
(Hoffman, 1991; Ogden 1992a, 1992b, 1994; Spezzano, 1993
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.