PHILOSOPHY
OF ECONOMIC GROW & IT’S IMPLICATIONS FOR BUSINESS
Introduction:
What is Economics?
Both the definition and the precise
domain of economics are subjects of controversy within philosophy of economics.
At first glance, the difficulties in defining economics may not appear serious.
Economics is, after all, concerned with aspects of the production, exchange,
distribution, and consumption of commodities. But this claim and the terms it
contains are vague; and it is arguable that economics is relevant to a great
deal more. It helps to approach the question, ―What is economics?‖
historically, before turning to comments on contemporary features of the
discipline.
The
emergence of economics and of economies
Philosophical reflection on
economics is ancient, but the conception of the economy as a distinct object of
study dates back only to the 18th century. Aristotle addresses some problems
that most would recognize as pertaining to economics mainly as problems
concerning how to manage a household. Scholastic philosophers addressed ethical
questions concerning economic behavior, and they condemned usury — that is, the
taking of interest on money. With the increasing importance of trade and of
nation-states in the early modern period, ‗mercantilist‘ philosophers and
pamphleteers were largely concerned with the balance of trade and the
regulation of the currency. There was an increasing recognition of the
complexities of the financial management of the state and of the possibility
that the way that the state taxed and acted influenced the production of
wealth.
In the Twentieth Century, economists
stripped this general theory of rationality of its hedonistic clothing (Pareto 1909,
Hicks and Allen 1934). Rather than supposing that all consumption choices can
be ranked by how much they promote an agent's happiness, economists focused on
the ranking itself. All that they suppose concerning evaluations is that agents
are able consistently to rank the alternatives they face. This is equivalent to
supposing first that rankings are complete — that is, for any two alternatives
x and y that the agent may evaluate or choose, either the agent ranks x above y
(prefers x to y), or the agent prefers y to x, or the agent is indifferent.
Second, economists suppose that agent's rankings of alternatives (preferences)
are transitive. To say that an agent's preferences are transitive is to claim
that if the agent prefers x to y and y to z, then the agent prefers x to z,
with similar claims concerning indifference and
An Essay on the Nature and
Significance of Economic Science, Lionel Robbins defined economics as ―the
science which studies human behavior as a relationship between ends and scarce
means which have alternative uses‖ (1932, p. 15). According to Robbins,
economics is not concerned with production, exchange, distribution, or
consumption as such. It is instead concerned with an aspect of all human
action. Although Robbins' definition helps one to understand efforts to apply
economic concepts, models, and techniques to other subject matters such as the
analysis of voting behavior and legislation, it seems evident that economics
maintains its connection to a traditio nal domain.
Contemporary
economics and its several schools
Contemporary economics is extremely
diverse. There are many schools and many branches. Even so-called ―orthodox‖ or
―mainstream‖ economics has many variants. Some mainstream economics is highly
theoretical, though most of it is applied and relies on only rather rudimentary
theory. Both theoretical and applied work can be distinguished as
microeconomics or macroeconomics. Microeconomics focuses on relations among
individuals (though firms and households often count as honorary individuals
and little is said about the demand of particular individuals for specific
commodities as opposed to aggregate demand for those commodities). Individuals
have complete and transitive preferences that govern their choices. Consumers
prefer more commodities to fewer and have ―diminishing marginal rates of
substitution‖ — i. e. they will pay less for units of a commodity when they
already have lots of it than when they have little of it. Firms attempt to
maximize profits in the face of diminishing returns: holding fixed all the
inputs into production except one, output increases when there is more of the
remaining input, but at a diminishing rate.
Economists idealize and suppose that
in competitive markets, firms and individuals cannot influence prices, but
economists are also interested in strategic interactions, in which the rational
choices of separate individuals are interdependent. Game theory, which is
devoted to the study of strategic interactions, is of growing importance both
in theoretical and applied microeconomics. Economists model the outcome of the
profit- maximizing activities of firms and the attempts of consumers to best
satisfy their preferences as an equilibrium
in which there is no excess demand on any market. What this means is that
anyone who wants to buy anything at the going market price is able to do so.
There is no excess demand, and unless a good is free, there is no excess
supply.
Macroeconomics grapples with the
relations among economic aggregates, such as relations between the money supply
and the rate of interest or the rate of growth, focusing especially on problems
concerning the business cycle and the influence of monetary and fiscal policy
on economic outcomes. Many mainstream economists would like to unify macroeconomics
and microeconomics, but few economists are satisfied with the attempts that
have been made to do so, especially via so called ―representative agents‖
(Kirman 1992, Hoover 2001a). Econometrics is a third main branch of economics,
devoted to the empirical estimation, elaboration, and to some extent testing of
specific microeconomic and macroeconomic models (but see summers 1991 and
Hoover 1994). Macroeconomics is immediately relevant to economic policy and
hence (and unsurprisingly) subjects to much more heated (and politically-
charged) controversy than microeconomics or econometrics.
Six
central methodological problems
Although the different branches and
schools of economics raise a wide variety of epistemological and ontological
issues concerning economics, six problems have been central to methodological
reflection (in this philosophical sense) concerning economics:
Positive
versus normative economics
Policy makers look to economics to
guide policy, and it seems inevitable that even the most esoteric issues in
theoretical economics may bear on some people's material interests. The extent
to which economics bears on and may be influenced by normative concerns raises
methodological questions about the relationships between a positive science concerning ―facts‖ and a normative inquiry into
values and what ought to be. Most economists and methodologists believe that
there is a reasonably clear distinction between facts and values, between what
is and what ought to be, and they believe that most of economics should be
regarded as a positive science that helps policy makers choose means to
accomplish their ends, though it does not bear on the choice of ends itself.
This view is questionable for
several reasons (Mongin 2006, Hausman and McPherson 2006). First economists
have to interpret and articulate the incomplete specifications of goals and
constraints provided by policy makers (Machlup 1969b). Second, econo mic
―science‖ is a human activity, and like all human activities, it is governed by
values. Those values need not be the same as the values that influence economic
policy, but it is debatable whether the values that govern the activity of
economists can be sharply distinguished from the values that govern policy
makers. Third, much of economics is built around a normative theory of
rationality. One can question whether the values implicit in such theories are
sharply distinguishable from the values that govern policies. For example, it
may be difficult to hold a maximizing view of individual rationality, while at
the same time insisting that social policy should resist maximizing growth,
wealth, or welfare in the name of freedom, rights, or equality. Fourth,
people's views of what is right and wrong are, as a matter of fact, influenced
by their beliefs about how people in fact behave. There is evidence that
studying theory that depicts individuals as self- interested leads people to
regard self- interested behavior more favorably and to become more self-
interested (Marwell and Ames 1981, Frank et
al. 1993).
Reasons
versus causes
Orthodox theoretical microeconomics
is as much a theory of rational choices as it a theory that explains and
predicts economic outcomes. Since virtually all economic theories that discuss
individual choices take individuals as acting for reasons, and thus in some way
rational, questions about the role that views of rationality and reasons should
play in economics are of general importance. Economists are typically concerned
with the aggregate results of individual choices rather than with particular
individuals, but their theories in fact offer both causal explanations for why
individuals choose as they do and accounts of the reasons for their choices.
See also the entry on Methodological Individualism.
Explanations in terms of reasons
have several features that distinguish them from explanations in terms of
causes. Reasons justify the actions they explain, and indeed so called
―external reasons‖ (Williams 1981)
only justify action, without purporting to explain it. Reasons can be
evaluated, and they are responsive to criticism. Reasons, unlike causes, must
be intelligible to those for whom they are reasons.
Social
scientific naturalism
Of all the social sciences,
economics most closely resembles the natural sciences. Economic theories have
been axiomatized, and articles and books of economics are full of theorems. Of
all the social sciences, only economics boasts an ersatz Nobel Prize. Economics
is thus a test case for those concerned with the extent of the similarities
between the natural and social sciences. Those who have wondered whether social
sciences must differ fundamentally from the natural sciences seem to have been concerned
mainly with three questions:
(i) Are there fundamental
differences between the structure or concepts of theories and explanations in the natural and social sciences? Some of these issues
were already mentioned in the discussion above of reasons versus causes.
(ii) Are there fundamental
differences in goals? Philosophers and economists have argued that in addition
to or instead of the predictive and explanatory goals of the natural sciences,
the social sciences should aim at providing us with understanding. Weber and others have argued that the social
sciences should provide us with an understanding ―from the inside‖, that we
should be able to empathize with the reactions of the agents and to find what
happens ―understandable‖ (Weber 1904, Knight 1935, Machlup 1969a). This (and
the closely related recognition that explanations cite reasons rather than just
causes) seems to introduce an element of subjectivity into the social sciences
that is not found in the natural sciences.
(iii) Owing to the importance of
human choices (or perhaps free will), are social phenomena too ―irregular‖ to
be captured within a framework of laws and theories? Given human free will,
perhaps human behavior is intrinsically unpredictable and not subject to any
laws. But there is, in fact, much regularity in human action, and given the
enormous causal complexity characterizing some natural systems, the natural
sciences must cope with many irregularities, too.
Abstraction,
idealization, and ceteris paribus clauses in economics
Economics raises questions
concerning the legitimacy of severe abstraction and idealization. For example,
mainstream economic models often stipulate that everyone is perfectly rational
and has perfect information or that commodities are infinitely divisible. Such
claims are exaggerations, and they are clearly false. Other schools of
economics may not employ idealizations that are this extreme, but there is no
way to do economics if one is not willing to simplify drastically and abstract
from many complications. How much simplification, idealization, abstraction or
―isolation‖ (Mäki
2006) is legitimate?
In addition, because economists
attempt to study economic phenomena as constituting a separate domain,
influenced only by a small number of causal factors, the claims of economics
are true only ceteris paribus — that is, they are true only if there
are no interferences or disturbing causes. What are ceteris paribus
clauses, and when if ever are they legitimate in science? Questions concerning ceteris paribus clauses are closely
related to questions concerning simplifications and idealizations, since one
way to simplify is to suppose that the various disturbing causes or
interferences are inactive and to explore the consequences of some small number
of causal factors. These issues and the related question of how well supported
economics is by the evidence has been the central questions in economic
methodology. They will be discussed further below in Section 3 and elsewhere.
Causation in economics and econometrics
Many important generalizations in
economics are causal claims. For example, the law of demand asserts that a
price increase will (ceteris paribus) diminish the quantity demanded. (It does
not merely assert an inverse relationship between price and demand. When demand
increases for some other reason, such as a change in tastes, price increases.)
Econometricians have also been deeply concerned with the possibilities of
determining causal relations from statistical evidence and with the relevance
of causal relations to the possibility of consistent estimation of parameter
values. Since concerns about the consequences of alternative policies are so
central to economics, causal inquiry is unavoidable.
Before the 1930s, economists were
generally willing to use causal language explicitly and literally, despite some
concerns that there might be a conflict between causal analysis of economic
changes and ―comparative statics‖ treatments of equilibrium states. Some
economists were also worried that thinking in terms of causes was not
compatible with recognizing the multiplic ity and mutuality of determination in
economic equilibrium. In the anti- metaphysical intellectual environment of the
1930s and 1940s (of which logical positivism was at least symptomatic), any
mention of causation became highly suspicious, and economists commonly
pretended to avoid causal concepts. The consequence was that they ceased to
reflect carefully on the causal concepts that they continued implicitly to
invoke (Hausman 1983, 1990, Helm 1984, Runde 1998). For example, rather than
formulating the law of demand in terms of the causal consequences of price
changes for quantity demanded, economists tried to confine themselves to
discussing the mathematical function relating price and quantity demanded.
There were important exceptions (Haavelmo 1944, Simon 1953, Wold 1954), and
during the past generation, this state of affairs has changed dramatically.
For example, in his Causality in
Macroeconomics (2001b) Kevin Hoover develops feasible methods for investigating
large scale causal questions, such as whe ther changes in the money supply
(M) cause changes in the rate of
inflation P or accommodate changes in P that are otherwise caused. If changes
in M cause changes in P, then the conditional distribution of P on M should
remain stable with exogenous changes in M, but should change with exogenous
changes in P. Hoover argues that historical investigation, backed by statistical
inquiry, can justify the conclusion that some particular changes in M or P have
been exogenous. One can then determine the causal direction by examining the
stability of the conditional distributions. Econometricians have made vital
contributions to the contemporary revival of philosophical interest in the
notion of causation. I n addition to Hoover's work, see for example Geweke
(1982), Granger (1969, 1980), Cartwright (1989), Sims (1977), Zellner and
Aigner (1988), Pearl (2000), Spirtes, Glymour and Scheines (2001).
One apparently secure way to
determine causal relations is via randomized controlled experiments. If the
experimenter‘s sorts subjects randomly into experimental and control groups and
varies just one factor, then unless by bad luck the two groups differ in some
unknown way, changes in the outcomes given the common features of the control
and treatment groups should be due to the difference in the one factor. This
makes randomized controlled trials very attractive, though no panacea, since the
treatment and control groups may not be representative of the population in
which policy- makers hope to apply the causal conclusions, and the causal
consequences of the intervention might differ across different subgroups within
the control and treatment groups (Worrall 2007).
Structure
and strategy of economics: paradigms and research programmes
In the wake of the work of Kuhn
(1970) and Lakatos (1970), philosophers are much more aware of and interested
in the larger theoretical structures that unify and guide researc h within
particular research traditions. Since many theoretical projects or approaches
in economics are systematically unified, they pose questions about what guides
research, and many economists have applied the work of Kuhn or Lakatos in the
attempt to s hed light on the overall structure of economics (Baumberg 1977,
Blaug 1976, de Marchi and Blaug 1991, Bronfenbrenner 1971, Coats 1969, Dillard
1978, Hands 1985b, Hausman 1992, ch. 6, Hutchison 1978, Latsis 1976, Jalladeau
1978, Kunin and Weaver 1971, Stanfield 1974, Weintraub 1985, Worland 1972).
Whether these applications have been successful is controversial, but the
comparison of the structure of economics to Kuhn's and Lakatos' schema has at
least served to highlight distinctive features of economics. For example,
asking what the ―positive heuristic‖ of mainstream economics consists in
permits one to see that mainstream models typically attempt to demonstrate that
an economic equilibrium will obtain, and thus that mainstream models are unified
in more than just their common assumptions. Since the success of research
projects in economics is controversial, understanding their global structure
and strategy may clarify their drawbacks as well as their advantages.
Inexactness,
ceteris paribus clauses, and “unrealistic assumptions”
As mentioned in the previous
section, the most important methodological issue concerning economics involves
the very considerable simplification, idealization, and abstraction that
characterizes economic theory and the consequent doubts these features of
economics raise concerning whether economics is well supported. Claims such as,
―Agents prefer larger commodity bundles to smaller commodity bundles,‖ raise
serious questions, because if they are interpreted as universal
generalizations, they are false. Can a science rest on false generalizations?
If these claims are not universal generalizations, then what is their logical
form? And how can claims that appear in this way to be false or approximate be
tested and confirmed or disconfirmed? These problems have bedeviled economists
and economic methodologists from the first methodological reflections to the
present day.
Classical economics and the method a priori
The first extended reflections on
economic methodology appear in the work of Nassau Senior (1836) and John Stuart
Mill (1836). Their essays must be understood against the background of the
economic theory of their times. Like Smith's economics (to which it owed a
great deal) and modern economics, the ―classical‖ economics of the middle
decades of the 19th century traced economic regularities to the choices of
individuals facing social and natural constraints. But, as compared to Smith,
more reliance was placed on severely simplified models.
David Ricardo's Principles of
Political Economy (1817) draws a portrait in which wages above the subsistence
level lead to increases in the population, which in turn require more intensive
agriculture or cultivation of inferior land. The extension of cultivation leads
to lo wer profits and higher rents; and the whole tale of economic development
leads to a gloomy stationary state in which profits are too low to command any
net investment, wages return to subsistence levels, and only the landlords are
affluent.
Fortunately for the world, but
unfortunately for economic theorists at the time, the data consistently
contradicted the trends the theory predicted (de Marchi 1970). Yet the theory
continued to hold sway for more than half a century and the consistently
unfavorable data were explained away as due to various ―disturbing causes.‖ It
is consequently not surprising that Senior's and Mill's accounts of the method
of economics emphasize the relative autonomy of theory.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.