MAIN
FEATURES OF A ECONOMIC PLANNING WITH RESPECT TO BUSINESS
Main Features of a Planned Economy
If we have a look at the planned economies, say, Russian, Chinese or even
Indian economy, we shall discover some characteristics. The formulation of the
plan and its implementation call for a certain type of economic and
administrative organization and a certain type of endeavor and set- up. It is
only natural, therefore, that the planned economies reveal some common
features.
1.
Existence of a Central Planning Authority. All countries launching on economic planning have at the top of economic affairs a
Planning Commission or a Central Planning Authority, e.g., Gosplan in the
U.S.S.R. and a Planning Commission in India. Planning has no meaning unless it
is centrally planned.
Planning by individual industries or
organization will simply constitute plans and no planning.
2. Laying Down Objectives. Planning to be fruitful must keep steadily
in view certain broad objectives which have to be realized. In the absence of
such objectives planning will be merely a leap in the dark. Planning is not a
policy of drift and the economic endeavor under planning has not to be
haphazard.
Certain very desirable objectives
are laid down beforehand. The usual objectives are the maximization of national
income, rapid industrialization providing full employment, achieving a
socialistic pattern, achieving self- sufficiency, etc. Of course, the
objectives will be laid down in the context of the economic situation.
3.
Fixed targets- Allied
with the laying down of the
objectives is the fixing of targets. The
objectives indicate the directions
in which the economy is to move and targets are fixed for the realization of
those objectives. Targets are fixed for each industry and for each sector of
major industries, transport, and communication, for imports and exports, and also
in the field of education and public health. Fixing of targets enables the
Planning Commission to determine the success or failure of each component part
of the economy.
4. Controls- A planned economy has of necessity to be subjected to a
variety of controls. The working of a free market economy has to be modified
and controlled in the interest of overall planned development. Thus, in a
planned economy we have price controls, control on the distribution of
essential goods and scarce raw materials, through fair price shops,
co-operative stores, import control, export control, exchange control, control
of capital issues, licensing of factories, etc. Laissez- faire is dead and gone
in all planned economies and extensive State control takes its place.
5. Co-ordination. Economic planning has to be comprehensive and not
isolated and piecemeal. All economic efforts aiming at accelerated economic
development must be properly coordinated. Without co-ordination a country will
land itself into chaos and economic mess.
6. Growing Public Sector. Another important feature of a planned
economy is the vital role played by the public sector and its growing
importance. Private sector cannot be expected to sink capital in enterprises in
which the return is long-delayed and is uncertain. The State as the custodian
of national interest must step in where private enterprise is shy and is found
wanting. The public sector really provides the essential framework for
spreading out the planned economic activity.
Better regional balance, more even
distribution of economic power, greater economic stability, greater employment,
fuller utilization of resources, greater security for the workers, elimination
of recurring business cycles are some other features of a planned economy.
MAIN
FEATURES OF ECONOMIC PLANNING WITH RESPECT TO BUSINESS:
The past half century has witnessed
the emergence of a large literature devoted to economic methodology. That
literature explores many methodological approaches and applies its conclusions
to many schools and branches of economics. Much of the literature focuses on
the fundamental theory of mainstream economics — the theory of the equilibria
resulting from constrained rational individual choice, but macroeconomics has
recently attracted increasing interest (Backhouse??). Since 1985, there has
been a journal Economic and Philosophy
devoted specifically to philosophy of economics, and since 1994 there has also
been a Journal of Economic Methodology.
This section will sample some of the methodological work of the past two
decades.
Popperian
approaches
Karl Popper's philosophy of science
has been influential among economists, as among other scientists. Popper
defends what he calls a falsificationist methodology (1968, 1969). Scientists should formulate theories that are ―logically
falsifiable‖ — that is, inconsistent with some possible observation reports.
―All crows are black‖ is logically falsifiable, since it is inconsistent with
(and would be falsified by) an observation report of a red crow. Popper insists
on falsifiability on the grounds that unfalsifiable claims that rule out no
observations are uninformative. They provide no guidance concerning what to
expect. Second, Popper maintains that scientists should subject theories to harsh
test and should be willing to reject them when they fail the tests. Third, sc
ientists should regard theories as at best interesting conjectures. Passing a
test does not confirm a theory or provide scientists with reason to believe it.
It only justifies continuing to employ it (since it has not yet been falsified)
and devoting increased efforts to attempting to falsify it (since it has thus
far survived testing). Popper has also written in defense of what he calls
―situational logic‖ (which is basically rational choice theory) as the correct
method for the social sciences (1967, 1976). There appear to be serious
tensions between Popper's falsifications and his defense of situational logic,
and his discussion of situational logic has not been as influential as his
falsifications.
The
Rhetoric of Economics
One radical reaction to the
difficulties of justifying the reliance on severe simplifications is to deny
that economics passes methodological muster. Alexander Rosenberg (1992)
maintains that economics can only make imprecise generic predictions, and it ca
nnot make progress, because it is built around folk psychology, which is a
mediocre theory of human behavior and which (owing to the irreducibility of
intentional notions) cannot be improved. Complex economic theories are valuable
only as applied mathematics, not as empirical theory. Since economics does not
show the same consistent progress as the natural sciences, one cannot dismiss
Rosenberg's suggestion that economics is an empirical dead end. But his view
that it has made no progress and that it does not permit quantitative
predictions is hard to accept. For example, contemporary economists are much
better at pricing stock options than economists were even a generation ago.
An equally radical but opposite
reaction is Deirdre McCloskey's, who denies that there are any non-trivial
methodological standards that economics must meet (1985, 1994). In her view,
the only relevant and significant criteria for assessing the practices and
products of a discipline are those accepted by the practitioners. Apart from a
few general standards such as honesty and a willingness to listen to
criticisms, the only justifiable criteria for any conversation are those of the
participants. Economists can thus dismiss arrogant pretensions of philosophers
to judge economic discourse. Whatever a group of respected economists takes to
be good economics is automatically good economics. Philosophical standards of
empirical success are just so much hot air. Those who are interested in
understanding the character of economics and in contributing to its improvement
should eschew methodology and study instead the ―rhetoric‖ of economics — that
is, the means of argument and persuasion that succeed among economists.
McCloskey's studies of the rhetoric
of economics have been valuable and influential (1985, esp. ch. 5–7), but much
of her work consists not of such studies but of philosophical critiques of
economic methodology.
These are more problematic, because
the position sketched in the previous paragraph is hard to defend and
potentially self-defeating. It is hard to defend, because epistemological
standards for good science have already infected the conversation of
economists. The standards of predictive success which lead one to have qualms
about economics are already standards that many economists accept. The only way
to escape these doubts is to surrender the standards that gave rise to them.
But McCloskey's position undermines any principled argument for a change in
standards. Furthermore, as Alexander Rosenberg has argued (1988), it seems that
economists would doom themselves to irrelevance if they were to surrender
standards of predictive success, for it is upon such standards that policy
decisions are made.
McCloskey does not, in fact, want to
preclude all criticisms that economists are sometimes persuaded when they
should not be or are not persuaded when they should be. For she herself
criticizes the bad habit some economists have of conflating statistical
significance with economic importance (1985, ch. 9). Sometimes McCloskey
characterizes rhetoric descriptively as the study of what in fact persuades,
but sometimes she characterizes it normatively as the study of what ought to
persuade (1985, ch. 2). And if rhetoric is the study of what ought rationally
to persuade, then it is methodology, not an alternative to methodology.
Questions about whether economics is a successful empirical science cannot be
conjured away.
Realism
in economic methodology
Economic methodologist have paid
little attention to debates within philosophy of science between realists and
anti-realists (van Fraassen 1980, Boyd 1984), because economic theories rarely
postulate the existence of unobservable entities or properties, apart from
variants of ―everyday unobservables,‖ such as beliefs and desires.
Methodologists have, on the other hand, vigorously debated the goals of
economics, but those who argue that the ultimate goals are predictive (such as
Milton Friedman) do so because of their interest in policy, not because they
seek to avoid or resolve epistemological and semantic puzzles concerning
references to unobservables.
Nevertheless there are two important
recent realist programs in economic methodology. The first, developed mainly by
Uskali Mäki, is devoted to exploring the varieties of realism implicit in the
methodological statements and theoretical enterprises of economists (see Mäki
1990a, b, c, 2007). The second, which is espoused by Tony Lawson and his
co-workers, mainly at Cambridge University, derives from the work of Roy
Bhaskar (1978) (see Lawson 1997, Bhaskar et
al. 1998, and Fleetwood 1999). In Lawson's view, one can trace many of the
inadequacies of mainstream economics (of which he is a critic) to an
insufficient concern with ontology. In attempting to identify regularities on
the surface of the phenomena, mainstream economists are doomed to failure.
Economic phenomena are in fact influenced by a large number of different causal
factors, and one can achieve scientific knowledge only of the underlying
mechanisms and tendencies, whose operation can be glimpsed intermittently and
obscurely in observable relations. Mäki's and Lawson's programs obviously have
little to do with one another, though Mäki (like Mill, Cartwright, and Hausman)
shares Lawson's and Bhaskar's concern with underlying causal mecha nisms. See
also the entry on Scientific Realism.
Economic
methodology and social studies of science
Throughout its history, economics
has been the subject of sociological as well as methodological scrutiny. Many
sociological discussions of economics, like Marx's critique of classical
political economy, have been concerned to identify ideological distortions and
thereby to criticize particular aspects of economic theory and economic policy.
Since every political program finds economists who testify to its economic
virtues, there is a never-ending source of material for such critiques. For
example, in the wake of the near collapse of the international financial system
in 2008, American economists who argued for austerity were mostly Republicans,
while those who defended efforts to increase aggregate demand were mostly
Democrats.
The influence of contemporary
sociology of science and social studies of science, coupled with the
difficulties methodologists have had making sense of and rationalizing the
conduct of economics, have led to a sociological turn within methodological
reflection itself. Rather than showing that there is good evidence supporting
developments in economic theory or that those developments have other broadly
epistemic virtues, methodologists and historians such as D. Wade Hands (2001);
Hands and Mirowski 1998), Philip Mirowski (2002), and E. Roy Weintraub (1991)
have argued that these changes reflect a wide variety of non-rational factors,
from changes in funding for theoretical economics, political commitments,
personal rivalries, attachments to metaphors, or mathematical interests.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.