Breughel
Most of
our mistakes are fundamentally grammatical. We create our own difficulties by
employing an inadequate language to describe facts. Thus, to take one example,
we are constantly giving the same name to more than one thing, and more than
one name to the same thing. The results, when we come to argue, are deplorable.
For we are using a language which does not adequately describe the things about
which we are arguing.
The
word "painter" is one of those names whose indiscriminate application
has led to the worst results. All those who, for whatever reason and with
whatever intentions, put brushes to canvas and make pictures, are called
without distinction, painters. Deceived by the uniqueness of the name,
aestheticians have tried to make us believe that there is a single
painter-psychology, a single function of painting, a single standard of
criticism. Fashion changes and the views of art critics with it. At the present
time it is fashionable to believe in form to the exclusion of subject. Young
people almost swoon away with excess of aesthetic emotion before a Matisse. Two
generations ago they would have been wiping their eyes before the latest
Landseer. (Ah, those more than human, those positively Christ-like dogs - how
they moved, what lessons they taught! There had been no religious painting like
Landseer's since Carlo Dolci died.)
These
historical considerations should make us chary of believing too exclusively in
any single theory of art. One kind of painting, one set of ideas are
fashionable at any given moment. They are made the basis of a theory which
condemns all other kinds of painting and all preceding critical theories. The
process constantly repeats itself.
At
the present moment, it is true, we have achieved an unprecedently tolerant
eclecticism. We are able, if we are up-to-date, to enjoy everything, from Negro
sculpture to Locca della Robbia and from Magnasco to Byzantine mosaics. But it
is an eclecticism achieved at the expense of almost the whole content of the
various works of art considered. What we have learned to see in all these works
is their formal qualities, which we abstract and arbitrarily call essential.
The subject of the work, with all that the painter desired to express in it
beyond his feelings about formal relations, contemporary criticism rejects as
unimportant. The young painter scrupulously avoids introducing into his
pictures anything that might be mistaken for a story, or the expression of a
view of life, while the young Kunstforscher turns, as though at an act
of exhibitionism, from any manifestation by a contemporary of any such
forbidden interest in drama or philosophy. True, the old masters are
indulgently permitted to illustrate stories and express their thoughts about
the world. Poor devils, they knew no better! Your modern observer makes
allowance for their ignorance and passes over in silence all that is not a
matter of formal relations. The admirers of Giotto (as numerous today as were
the admirers of Guido Reni a hundred years ago) contrive to look at the
master's frescoes without considering what they represent, or what the painter
desired to express. Every germ of drama or meaning is disinfected out of them;
only the composition is admired. The process is analogous to reading Latin
verses without understanding them - simply for the sake of the rhythmical
rumbling of the hexameters.
It
would be absurd, of course, to deny the importance of formal relations. No
picture can hold together without composition and no good painter is without
some specific passion for form as such - just as no good writer is without a
passion for words and the arrangement of words. It is obvious that no man can
adequately express himself, unless he takes an interest in the terms which he
proposes to use as his medium of expression. Not all painters are interested in
the same sort of forms. Some, for example, have a passion for masses and the
surfaces of solids. Others delight in lines. Some compose in three dimensions.
Others like to make silhouettes on the flat. Some like to make the surface of the
paint smooth and, as it were, translucent, so that the objects represented in
the picture can be seen distinct and separate, as through a sheet of glass.
Others (as for example Rembrandt) love to make a rich thick surface which shall
absorb and draw together into one whole all the objects represented, and that
in spite of the depth of the composition and the distance of the objects from
the plane of the picture. All these purely aesthetic considerations are, as I
have said, important. All artists are interested in them; but almost none are
interested in them to the exclusion of everything else. It is very seldom
indeed that we find a painter who can be inspired merely by his interest in
form and texture to paint a picture. Good painters of "abstract" subjects
or even of still lives are rare. Apples and solid geometry do not stimulate a
man to express his feelings about form and make a composition. All thoughts and
emotions are interdependent. In the words of the dear old song,
The roses round the door
Make me love mother more.
One
feeling is excited by another. Our faculties work best in a congenial emotional
atmosphere. For example, Mantegna's faculty for making noble arrangements of
forms was stimulated by his feelings about heroic and god-like humanity.
Expressing those feelings, which he found exciting, he also expressed - and in
the most perfect manner of which he was capable - his feelings about masses,
surfaces, solids, and voids. "The roses round the door" - his hero
worship - "made him love mother more" - made him, by stimulating his
faculty for composition, paint better. If Isabella d'Este had made him paint
apples, table napkins and bottles, he would have produced, being uninterested
in these objects, a poor composition. And yet, from a purely formal point of
view, apples, bottles and napkins are quite as interesting as human bodies and
faces. But Mantegna - and with him the majority of painters - did not happen to
be very passionately interested in these inanimate objects. When one is bored one
becomes boring.
The apples round the door
Make me a frightful bore.
Inevitably;
unless I happen to be so exclusively interested in form that I can paint
anything that has a shape; or unless I happen to possess some measure of that
queer pantheism, that animistic superstition which made Van Gogh regard the
humblest of common objects as being divinely or devilishly alive. "Crains
dans le mur aveugle un regard qui t'épie." If a painter can do that, he will
be able, like Van Gogh, to make pictures of cabbage fields and the bedrooms of
cheap hotels that shall be as wildly dramatic as a Rape of the Sabines.
The
contemporary fashion is to admire beyond all others the painter who can
concentrate on the formal side of his art and produce pictures which are entirely
devoid of literature. Old Renoir's apophthegm, "Un peintre, voyez-vous,
qui a le sentiment du téton et des fesses, est un homme sauvé," is considered by the purists suspiciously
latitudinarian. A painter who has the sentiment of the pap and the buttocks is
a painter who portrays real models with gusto. Your pure aesthete should only
have a feeling for hemispheres, curved lines and surfaces. But this
"sentiment of the buttocks" is common to all good painters. It is the
lowest common measure of the whole profession. It is possible, like Mantegna,
to have a passionate feeling for all that is solid, and at the same time to be
a stoic philosopher and a hero-worshiper; possible, with Michelangelo, to have
a complete realization of breasts and also an interest in the soul or, like
Rubens, to have a sentiment for human greatness as well as for human rumps. The
greater includes the less; great dramatic or reflective painters know
everything that the aestheticians who paint geometrical pictures, apples or buttocks
know, and a great deal more besides. What they have to say about formal
relations, though important, is only a part of what they have to express. The
contemporary insistence on form to the exclusion of everything else is an
absurdity. So was the older insistence on exact imitation and sentiment to the
exclusion of form. There need be no exclusions. In spite of the single name,
there are many different kinds of painters and all of them, with the exception
of those who cannot paint, and those whose minds are trivial, vulgar and
tedious, have a right to exist.
All
classifications and theories are made after the event; the facts must first
occur before they can be tabulated and methodized. Reversing the historical
process, we attack the facts forearmed with theoretical prejudice. Instead of
considering each fact on its own merits, we ask how it fits into the
theoretical scheme. At any given moment a number of meritorious facts fail to
fit into the fashionable theory and have to be ignored. Thus El Greco's art
failed to conform with the ideal of good painting held by Philip the Second and
his contemporaries. The Sienese primitives seemed to the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries incompetent barbarians. Under the influence of Ruskin, the
later nineteenth century contrived to dislike almost all architecture that was
not Gothic. And the early twentieth century, under the influence of the French,
deplores and ignores, in painting, all that is literary, reflective or
dramatic.
In
every age theory has caused men to like much that was bad and reject much that
was good. The only prejudice that the ideal art critic should have is against
the incompetent, the mentally dishonest and the futile. The number of ways in
which good pictures can be painted is quite incalculable, depending only on the
variability of the human mind. Every good painter invents a new way of
painting. Is this man a competent painter? Has he something to say, is he
genuine? These are the questions a critic must ask himself. Not, Does he
conform with my theory of imitation, or distortion, or moral purity, or
significant form?
There
is one painter against whom, it seems to me, theoretical prejudice has always
most unfairly told. I mean the elder Breughel. Looking at his best paintings I
find that I can honestly answer in the affirmative all the questions which a
critic may legitimately put himself. He is highly competent aesthetically; he
has plenty to say; his mind is curious, interesting and powerful; and he has no
false pretensions, is entirely honest. And yet he has never enjoyed the high
reputation to which his merits entitle him. This is due, I think, to the fact
that his work has never quite squared with any of the various critical theories
which since his days have had a vogue in the aesthetic world.
A
subtle colorist, a sure and powerful draftsman, and possessing powers of
composition that enable him to marshal the innumerable figures with which his
pictures are filled into pleasingly decorative groups (built up, as we see,
when we try to analyze his methods of formal arrangement, out of individually
flat, silhouette-like shapes standing in a succession of receding planes),
Breughel can boast of purely aesthetic merits that ought to endear him even to
the strictest sect of the Pharisees. Coated with this pure aesthetic jam, the
bitter pill of his literature might easily, one would suppose, be swallowed. If
Giotto's dalliance with sacred history be forgiven him, why may not Breughel be
excused for being an anthropologist and a social philosopher? To which I
tentatively answer: Giotto is forgiven, because we have so utterly ceased to
believe in Catholic Christianity that we can easily ignore the subject matter
of his pictures and concentrate only on their formal qualities; Breughel, on
the other hand, is unforgivable because he made comments on humanity that are
still interesting to us. From his subject matter we cannot escape; it touches
us too closely to be ignored. That is why Breughel is despised by all
up-to-date Kunstforschers.
And
even in the past, when there was no theoretical objection to the mingling of
literature and painting, Breughel failed, for another reason, to get his due.
He was considered low, gross, a mere comedian, and as such unworthy of serious
consideration. Thus, the Encyclopedia Britannica, which in these matters
may be safely relied on to give the current opinion of a couple of generations
ago, informs us, in the eleven lines which it parsimoniously devotes to Peter
Breughel that "the subjects of his pictures are chiefly humorous figures,
like those of D. Teniers; and if he wants the delicate touch and silvery
clearness of that master, he has abundant spirit and comic power."
Whoever
wrote these words - and they might have been written by any one desirous, fifty
years ago, of playing for safety and saying the right thing - can never have
taken the trouble to look at any of the pictures painted by Breughel when he
was a grown and accomplished artist.
In
his youth, it is true, he did a great deal of hack work for a dealer who
specialized in caricatures and devils in the manner of Hieronymus Bosch. But
his later pictures, painted when he had really mastered the secrets of his art,
are not comic at all. They are studies of peasant life, they are allegories,
they are religious pictures of the most strangely reflective cast, they are
exquisitely poetical landscapes. Breughel died at the height of his powers. But
there is enough of his mature work in existence - at Antwerp, at Brussels, at
Naples and above all at Vienna - to expose the fatuity of the classical verdict
and exhibit him for what he was: the first landscape painter of his century,
the acutest student of manners, and the wonderfully skillful pictorial
expounder or suggester of a view of life. It is at Vienna, indeed, that
Breughel's art can best be studied in all its aspects. For Vienna possesses
practically all his best pictures of whatever kind. The scattered pictures at
Antwerp, Brussels, Paris, Naples and elsewhere give one but the faintest notion
of Breughel's powers. In the Vienna galleries are collected more than a dozen
of his pictures, all belonging to his last and best period. The Tower of Babel,
the great Calvary, the Numbering of the People at Bethlehem, the two Winter
Landscapes and the Autumn Landscape, the Conversion of Saint Paul, the Battle
between the Israelites and the Philistines, the Marriage Feast and the
Peasants' Dance - all these admirable works are here. It is on these that he
must be judged.
There
are four landscapes at Vienna: the Dark Day (January) and Huntsmen in the Snow
(February), a November landscape (the Return of the Cattle), and the Numbering
of the People at Bethlehem which in spite of its name is little more than a
landscape with figures. This last, like the February Landscape and the Massacre
of the Innocents at Brussels, is a study of snow. Snow scenes lent themselves
particularly well to Breughel's style of painting. For a snowy background has
the effect of making all dark or colored objects seen against it appear in the
form of very distinct, sharp-edged silhouettes. Breughel does in all his
compositions what the snow does in nature. All the objects in his pictures
(which are composed in a manner that reminds one very much of the Japanese) are
paper-thin silhouettes arranged, plane after plane, like the theatrical scenery
in the depth of the stage. Consequently in the painting of snow scenes, where
nature starts by imitating his habitual method, he achieves an almost
disquieting degree of fundamental realism. Those hunters stepping down over the
brow of the hill toward the snowy valley with its frozen ponds are Jack Frost
himself and his crew. The crowds who move about the white streets of Bethlehem
have their being in an absolute winter, and those ferocious troopers looting
and innocent-hunting in the midst of a Christmas card landscape are a part of
the very army of winter, and the innocents they kill are the young green shoots
of the earth.
Breughel's
method is less fundamentally compatible with the snowless landscapes of January
and November. The different planes stand apart a little too flatly and
distinctly. It needs a softer, bloomier kind of painting to recapture the
intimate quality of such scenes as those he portrays in these two pictures. A
born painter of Autumn, for example, would have fused the beasts, the men, the
trees and the distant mountains into a hazier unity, melting all together, the
near and the far, in the rich surface of his paint. Breughel painted too
transparently and too flatly to be the perfect interpreter of such landscapes.
Still, even in terms of his not entirely suitable convention he has done
marvels. The Autumn Day is a thing of the most exquisite beauty. Here, as in
the more somberly dramatic January Landscape, he makes a subtle use of golds
and yellows and browns, creating a sober yet luminous harmony of colors. The
November Landscape is entirely placid and serene; but in the Dark Day he has
staged one of those natural dramas of the sky and earth - a conflict between
light and darkness. Light breaks from under clouds along the horizon, shines up
from the river in the valley that lies in the middle distance, glitters on the
peaks of the mountains. The foreground, which represents the crest of a wooded
hill, is dark; and the leafless trees growing on the slopes are black against
the sky. These two pictures are the most beautiful sixteenth-century landscapes
of which I have any knowledge. They are intensely poetical, yet sober and not
excessively picturesque or romantic. Those fearful crags and beetling precipices
of which the older painters were so fond do not appear in these examples of
Breughel's maturest work.
Breughel's
anthropology is as delightful as his nature poetry. He knew his Flemings, knew
them intimately, both in their prosperity and during the miserable years of
strife, of rebellion, of persecution, of war and consequent poverty which
followed the advent of the Reformation in Flanders.
A
Fleming himself, and so profoundly and ineradicably a Fleming that he was able
to go to Italy, and, like his great countryman in the previous century, Roger
van der Weyden, return without the faintest tincture of Italianism - he was
perfectly qualified to be the natural historian of the Flemish folk. He
exhibits them mostly in those moments of orgiastic gaiety with which they
temper the laborious monotony of their daily lives: eating enormously,
drinking, uncouthly dancing, indulging in that peculiarly Flemish scatological
waggery. The Wedding Feast and the Peasants' Dance, both at Vienna, are superb
examples of this anthropological type of painting. Nor must we forget those two
curious pictures, the Battle between Carnival and Lent and the Children's
Games. They too show us certain aspects of the joyous side of Flemish life. But
the view is not of an individual scene, casually seized at its height and
reproduced. These two pictures are systematic and encyclopedic. In one he
illustrates all children's games; in the other all the amusements of carnival,
with all the forces arrayed on the side of asceticism. In the same way he
represents, in his extraordinary Tower of Babel, all the processes of building.
These pictures are handbooks of their respective subjects.
Breughel's
fondness for generalizing and systematizing is further illustrated in his
allegorical pieces. The Triumph of Death, at the Prado, is appalling in its
elaboration and completeness. The fantastic "Dulle Griet" at Antwerp
is an almost equally elaborate triumph of evil. His illustrations to proverbs
and parables belong to the same class. They show him to have been a man
profoundly convinced of the reality of evil and of the horrors which this
mortal life, not to mention eternity, hold in store for suffering humanity. The
world is a horrible place; but in spite of this, or precisely because of this,
men and women eat, drink and dance, Carnival tilts against Lent and triumphs,
if only for a moment; children play in the streets, people get married in the
midst of gross rejoicings.
But
of all Breughel's pictures the one most richly suggestive of reflection is not
specifically allegorical or systematic. Christ carrying the Cross is one of his
largest canvases, thronged with small figures rhythmically grouped against a
wide and romantic background. The composition is simple, pleasing in itself,
and seems to spring out of the subject instead of being imposed on it. So much
for pure aesthetics.
Of
the Crucifixion and the Carrying of the Cross there are hundreds of
representations by the most admirable and diverse masters. But of all that I
have ever seen this Calvary of Breughel's is the most suggestive and,
dramatically, the most appalling. For all other masters have painted these
dreadful scenes from within, so to speak, outwards. For them Christ is the
center, the divine hero of the tragedy; this is the fact from which they start;
it affects and transforms all the other facts, justifying, in a sense, the
horror of the drama and ranging all that surrounds the central figure in an
ordered hierarchy of good and evil. Breughel, on the other hand, starts from
the outside and works inwards. He represents the scene as it would have
appeared to any casual spectator on the road to Golgotha on a certain spring
morning in the year 33 A.D. Other
artists have pretended to be angels, painting the scene with a knowledge of its
significance. But Breughel resolutely remains a human onlooker. What he shows
is a crowd of people walking briskly in holiday joyfulness up the slopes of a
hill. On the top of the hill, which is seen in the middle distance on the
right, are two crosses with thieves fastened to them, and between them a little
hole in the ground in which another cross is soon to be planted. Round the
crosses, on the bare hill top stands a ring of people, who have come out with
their picnic baskets to look on at the free entertainment offered by the
ministers of justice. Those who have already taken their stand round the
crosses are the prudent ones; in these days we should see them with camp stools
and thermos flasks, six hours ahead of time, in the vanguard of the queue for a
Melba night at Covent Garden. The less provident or more adventurous people are
in the crowd coming up the hill with the third and greatest of the criminals
whose cross is to take the place of honor between the other two. In their
anxiety not to miss any of the fun on the way up, they forget that they will
have to take back seats at the actual place of execution. But it may be, of
course, that they have reserved their places, up there. At Tyburn one could get
an excellent seat in a private box for half a crown; with the ticket in one's
pocket, one could follow the cart all the way from the prison, arrive with the
criminal and yet have a perfect view of the performance. In these later days,
when cranky humanitarianism has so far triumphed that hangings take place in
private and Mrs. Thompson's screams are not even allowed to be recorded on the
radio, we have to be content with reading about executions, not with seeing
them. The impresarios who sold seats at Tyburn have been replaced by titled
newspaper proprietors who sell juicy descriptions of Tyburn to a prodigiously
much larger public. If people were still hanged at Marble Arch, Lord Riddell
would be much less rich.
That
eager, tremulous, lascivious interest in blood and beastliness which in these
more civilized days we can only satisfy at one remove from reality in the pages
of our newspapers, was franklier indulged in Breughel's day; the naïve ingenuous brute
in man was less sophisticated, was given longer rope, and joyously barks and
wags its tail round the appointed victim. Seen thus, impassively, from the
outside, the tragedy does not purge or uplift; it appalls and makes desperate;
or it may even inspire a kind of gruesome mirth. The same situation may often
be either tragic or comic, according as it is seen through the eyes of those
who suffer or those who look on. (Shift the point of vision a little and
Macbeth could be paraphrased as a roaring farce.) Breughel makes a concession
to the high tragic convention by placing in the foreground of his picture a
little group made up of the holy women weeping and wringing their hands. They
stand quite apart from the other figures in the picture and are fundamentally
out of harmony with them, being painted in the style of Roger van der Weyden. A
little oasis of passionate spirituality, an island of consciousness and
comprehension in the midst of the pervading stupidity and brutishness. Why
Breughel put them into his picture is difficult to guess; perhaps for the
benefit of the conventionally religious, perhaps out of respect for tradition;
or perhaps he found his own creation too depressing and added this noble
irrelevance to reassure himself.
(From Along the Road)
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.