BIOMEDICAL
ETHICS IN PHARMACOLOGY: AN INTRODUCTION AND FRAMEWORK
The relationship between
physicians, scientists, and the pharmaceutical industry is a mutually
advantageous one that is fraught with ethical complexity. Seemingly
straightforward questions, such as whether a physician ought to enroll patients
in a drug trial, which drug to prescribe when any one of several may be
effective, and how to stay abreast of new drugs while remaining ob-jective,
become difficult when examined closely
Bioethics is the study of
ethical issues associated with providing health care or pursuing biomedical
research. Most approaches to bioethics in the United States are secular in
nature and presuppose no particular religious or theological perspective. While
one’s religious beliefs may play an important role in determining personal
morality, the broader endeavor of bioethical analysis at-tempts to be devoid of
any particular religious perspec-tive. Similarly, bioethical analysis stands
independent of legal analysis. Although the law is often a consideration in
bioethical decision making, laws in themselves do not determine the morality of
an action. Laws are supposed to reflect a societal consensus on issues and are
estab-lished to set a minimum standard of behavior.
Thus, while religion and law
provide guidelines for acceptable actions, religious beliefs, and knowledge of
the law are frequently insufficient to guide moral ac-tion, in the realm of
health care. Solving problems that arise in the scientific and clinical
contexts requires knowledge of ethical principles and the methodology for
applying them. While bioethical analysis is multifac-torial, four moral
principles play key roles in establish-ing a basic framework. These principles
were developed from a pluralistic, albeit North American, framework. Although
not every problem will involve all four princi-ples of bioethics, an understanding
of the principles of autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice will
build a solid framework for critical analysis.
The principle of autonomy entails that persons should be treated as
inherently valuable individuals with the moral right to make decisions about
their own lives. To the extent that one’s actions and choices do not negatively
affect others, individuals with the capacity to make their own decisions should
be free to do as they wish, even if their choices are risky or harmful to them-selves.
The principle also entails that persons with di-minished autonomy, such as
those who are illiterate or retarded, deserve to have their interests
protected. Many moral obligations for professionals engaged in scientific
research or health care are derived from the principle of autonomy, such as the
physician– researcher’s obligation to fully inform potential re-search subjects
and respect the individual’s informed consent or informed refusal. This
obligation is founded on the principle that individuals are the appropriate
de-cision makers for choices that do not harm others.
The principle of beneficence entails helping people to further their
interests. As the primary moral principle quoted in medical codes and oaths,
the principle of beneficence is fundamental to the practice of medicine and
clinical research. For example, concerns about beneficence motivate physicians,
pharmacologists, phar-macists, and clinical investigators, all of whom share
the goal of conducting studies that will ultimately benefit society by
producing or refining effective treatments.
The principle of nonmaleficence asserts that profes-sionals have an
obligation to prevent harm or if harm is unavoidable, minimize that harm. This
principle plays an important role in clinical research, as it entails an
obli-gation to minimize risks to each participant. Moreover, drug approval
procedures, such as those implemented by the Food and Drug Administration
(FDA), are designed to protect patients from harm while ultimately
facilitat-ing the marketing of drugs that have maximal therapeu-tic benefits.
Thus the principles of beneficence and non-maleficence dictate that the overall
goal of scientific advancement cannot trump the duty to protect human subjects
of clinical research from harm.
The principle of justice states that individuals should be given what
they deserve, be that benefit or burden. Cases that are alike should be treated
similarly, and rel-evant distinctions should be drawn consistently. The
principle of justice does not specifically state what dis-tinctions are fair or
which criteria are reasonable; it sim-ply requires that, once criteria are
determined, they be applied fairly. Justice is important in many areas, such as
recruitment of research subjects for pharmaceutical studies. For example,
researchers must guard against distributing the burdens of participation
disproportion-ately among populations that are poorly equipped to give informed
consent, such as children or the mentally incompetent.
The principles of autonomy, beneficence,
nonmalefi-cence, and justice form a foundation for analysis of eth-ical
quandaries. In addition, a comprehensive ethical analysis will include
considerations of cultural and reli-gious diversity of patient–subjects, health
care providers and interpersonal relationships; an assessment of the
profession-based duties and obligations of the health care professionals,
including an examination of relevant professional oaths and codes; and an
analysis of rele-vantly similar previous bioethical dilemmas.
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.