Decentralization and
Self-Government
The
Anarchists propose that the state should be abolished; and in so far as it
serves as the instrument by means of which the ruling class preserves its
privileges; in so far as it is a device for enabling paranoiacs to satisfy
their lust for power and carry out their crazy dreams of glory, the state is
obviously worthy of abolition. But in complex societies like our own the state
has certain other and more useful functions to perform. It is clear, for example,
that in any such society there must be some organization responsible for
co-ordinating the activities of the various constituent groups; clear, too,
that there must be a body to which is delegated the power of acting in the name
of the society as a whole. If the word "state" is too unpleasantly
associated with ideas of domestic oppression and foreign war, with
irresponsible domination and no less irresponsible submission, then by all
means let us call the necessary social machinery by some other name. For the
present there is no general agreement as to what that name should be; I shall
therefore go on using the bad old word, until some better one is invented.
No
economic reform, however intrinsically desirable, can lead to desirable changes
in individuals and the society they constitute, unless it is carried through in
a desirable context and by desirable methods. So far as the state is concerned,
the desirable context for reform is decentralization and self-government all
round. The desirable methods for enacting reform are the methods of
non-violence.
Passing
from the general to the particular and the concrete, the rational idealist
finds himself confronted by the following questions. First, by what means can
the principle of self-government be applied to the daily lives of men and
women? Second, to what extent is the self-government of the component parts of
a society compatible with its efficiency as a whole? And, thirdly, if a central
organization is needed to coordinate the activities of the self-governing
parts, what is to prevent this organization from becoming a ruling oligarchy of
the kind with which we are only too painfully familiar?
The
technique for self-government all round, self-government for ordinary people in
their ordinary avocation, is a matter which we cannot profitably discuss unless
we have a clear idea of what may be called the natural history and psychology
of groups. Quantitatively, a group differs from a crowd in size; qualitatively,
in the kind and intensity of the mental life of the constituent individuals. A
crowd is a lot of people; a group is a few. A crowd has a mental life inferior
in intellectual quality and emotionally less under voluntary control than the
mental life of each of its members in isolation. The mental life of a group is
not inferior, either intellectually or emotionally, to the mental life of the
individual composing it and may, in favorable circumstances, actually be
superior.
The
significant psychological facts about the crowd are as follows. The tone of crowd
emotion is essentially orgiastic and dionysiac. In virtue of his membership of
the crowd, the individual is released from the limitations of his personality,
made free of the sub-personal, sub-human world of unrestrained feeling and
uncriticized belief. To be a member of a crowd is an experience closely akin to
alcoholic intoxication. Most human beings feel a craving to escape from the
cramping limitations of their ego, to take periodical holidays from their all
too familiar, all too squalid little selves. As they do not know how to travel
upwards from personality into a region of super-personality and as they are
unwilling, even if they do know, to fulfill the ethical, psychological and
physiological conditions of self-transcendence, they turn naturally to the
descending road, the road that leads down from personality to the darkness of
sub-human emotionalism and panic animality. Hence the persistent craving for
narcotics and stimulants, hence the never failing attraction of the crowd. The
success of the dictators is due in large measure to their extremely skillful
exploitation of the universal human need for escape from the limitations of
personality. Perceiving that people wished to take holidays from themselves in
sub-human emotionality, they have systematically provided their subjects with
the occasions for doing so. The Communists denounce religion as the opium of
the people; but all they have done is to replace this old drug by a new one of
similar composition. For the crowd round the relic of the saint they have
substituted the crowd at the political meeting; for religious processions,
military reviews and May Day parades. It is the same with Fascist dictators. In
all the totalitarian states the masses are persuaded, and, even compelled, to
take periodical holidays from themselves in the sub-human world of crowd
emotion. It is significant that while they encourage and actually command the
descent into sub-humanity, the dictators do all they can to prevent men from
taking the upward road from personal limitation, the road that leads toward
non-attachment to the "things of this world" and attachment to that
which is super-personal. The higher manifestations of religion are far more
suspect to the tyrants than the lower - and with reason. For the man who
escapes from egotism into super-personality has transcended his old idolatrous
loyalty, not only to himself, but also to the local divinities - nation, party,
class, deified boss. Self-transcendence, escape from the prison of the ego into
union with what is above personality, is generally accomplished in solitude.
That is why the tyrants like to herd their subjects into those vast crowds, in
which the individual is reduced to a state of intoxicated sub-humanity.
It is
time now to consider the group. The first question we must ask ourselves is
this: when does a group become a crowd? This is not a problem in verbal
definition; it is a matter of observation and experience. It is found
empirically that group activities and characteristic group feeling become increasingly
difficult when more than about twenty or less than about five individuals are
involved. Groups which come together for the purpose of carrying out a specific
job of manual work can afford to be larger than groups which meet for the
purpose of pooling information and elaborating a common policy, or which meet
for religious exercises, or for mutual comfort, or merely for the sake of
convivially "getting together." Twenty or even as many as thirty
people can work together and still remain a group. But these numbers would be
much too high in a group that had assembled for the other purposes I have
mentioned. It is significant that Jesus had only twelve apostles; that the
Benedictines were divided into groups of ten under a dean (Latin decanus from
Greek ten); that ten is the number of
individuals constituting a Communist cell. Committees of more than a dozen
members are found to be unmanageably large. Eight is the perfect number for a
dinner party. The most successful Quaker meetings are generally meetings at
which few people are present. Educationists agree that the most satisfactory
size for a class is between eight and fifteen. In armies, the smallest unit is
about ten. The witches' "coven" was a group of thirteen. And so on.
All evidence points clearly to the fact that there is an optimum size for
groups and that this optimum is round about ten for groups meeting for social,
religious or intellectual purposes and from ten to thirty for groups engaged in
manual work. This being so, it is clear that the units of self-government
should be groups of the optimum size. If they are smaller than the optimum,
they will fail to develop that emotional field which gives to group activity
its characteristic quality, while the available quantity of pooled information
and experience will be inadequate. If they are larger than the optimum, they
will tend to split into sub-groups of the optimum size or, if the constituent
individuals remain together in a crowd there will be a danger of their
relapsing into the crowd's sub-human stupidity and emotionality.
The
technique of industrial self-government has been discussed with a wealth of
concrete examples in a remarkable book by the French economist Hyacinthe
Dubreuil, entitled, A Chacun sa Chance. Among the writers on industrial
organization Dubreuil occupies a place apart; for he is almost the only one of
them who has himself had experience of factory conditions as a workman.
Accordingly, what he writes on the subject of industrial organization carries
an authority denied to the utterances of those who rely on second-hand
information as a basis for their theories. Dubreuil points out that even the
largest industries can be organized so as to consist of a series of
self-governing, yet co-ordinated, groups of, at the outside, thirty members.
Within the industry each one of such groups can act as a kind of
sub-contractor, undertaking to perform so much of such and such a kind of work
for such and such a sum. The equitable division of this sum among the
constituent members is left to the group itself, as is also the preservation of
discipline, the election of representatives and leaders. The examples which
Dubreuil quotes from the annals of industrial history and from his own
experience as a workman tend to show that this form of organization is
appreciated by the workers, to whom it gives a measure of independence even
within the largest manufacturing concern, and that in most cases it results in
increased efficiency of working. It possesses, as he points out, the further merit
of being a form of organization that educates those who belong to it in the
practice of co-operation and mutual responsibility.
Under
the present dispensation, the great majority of factories are little
despotisms, benevolent in some cases, malevolent in others. Even where
benevolence prevails, passive obedience is demanded of the workers, who are
ruled by overseers, not of their own election, but appointed from above. In
theory, they may be the subjects of a democratic state; but in practice they spend
the whole of their working lives as the subjects of a petty tyrant. Dubreuil's
scheme, if it were generally acted upon, would introduce genuine democracy into
the factory. And if some such scheme is not acted upon, it is of small moment
to the individual whether the industry in which he is working is owned by the
state, by a co-operative society, by a joint stock company or by a private
individual. Passive obedience to officers appointed from above is always
passive obedience, whoever the general in ultimate control may be. Conversely,
even if the ultimate control is in the wrong hands, the man who voluntarily
accepts rules in the making of which he has had a part, who obeys leaders he
himself has chosen, who has helped to decide how much and in what conditions he
himself and his companions shall be paid, is to that extent the free and
responsible subject of a genuinely democratic government, and enjoys those
psychological advantages which only such a form of government can give.
Of
modern wage-slaves, Lenin writes that they "remain to such an extent
crushed by want and poverty that they 'can't be bothered with democracy,' have
'no time for politics,' and in the ordinary peaceful course of events, the
majority of the population is debarred from participating in public political
life." This statement is only partially true. Not all those who can't be
bothered with democracy are debarred from political life by want and poverty.
Plenty of well-paid workmen and, for that matter, plenty of the wealthiest beneficiaries
of the capitalistic system, find that they can't be bothered with politics. The
reason is not economic, but psychological; has its source, not in environment,
but in heredity. People belong to different psycho-physiological types and are
endowed with different degrees of general intelligence. The will and ability to
take an effective interest in large-scale politics do not belong to all, or
even a majority of, men and women. Preoccupation with general ideas, with
things and people distant in space, with contingent events remote in future
time, is something which it is given to only a few to feel. "What's Hecuba
to him or he to Hecuba?" The answer in most cases is: Nothing whatsoever.
An improvement in the standard of living might perceptibly increase the number
of those for whom Hecuba meant something. But even if all were rich, there
would still be many congenitally incapable of being bothered with anything so
far removed from the warm, tangible facts of everyday experience. As things are
at present, millions of men and women come into the world disfranchised by
nature. They have the privilege of voting on long-range, large-scale political
issues; but they are congenitally incapable of taking an intelligent interest
in any but short-range, small-scale problems. Too often the framers of
democratic constitutions have acted as though man were made for democracy, not
democracy for man. The vote has been a kind of bed of Procrustes upon which,
however long their views, however short their ability, all human beings were
expected to stretch themselves. Not unnaturally, the results of this kind of
democracy have proved disappointing. Nevertheless, it remains true that
democratic freedom is good for those who enjoy it and that practice in
self-government is an almost indispensable element in the curriculum of man's
moral and psychological education. Human beings belong to different types; it
is therefore necessary to create different types of democratic and
self-governing institutions, suitable for the various kinds of men and women.
Thus, people with short-range, small-scale interests can find scope for their
kind of political abilities in self-governing groups within an industry, within
a consumer or producer cooperative, within the administrative machinery of the
parish, borough or county. By means of comparatively small changes in the
existing systems of local and professional organization it would be possible to
make almost every individual a member of some self-governing group. In this way
the curse of merely passive obedience could be got rid of, the vice of
political indolence cured and the advantages of responsible and active freedom
brought to all. In this context it is worth remarking on a very significant
change which has recently taken place in our social habits. Materially, this
change may be summed up as the decline of the community; psychologically, as
the decline of the community sense. The reasons for this double change are many
and of various kinds. Here are a few of the more important.
Birth
control has reduced the size of the average family and, for various reasons
which will be apparent later, the old habits of patriarchal living have
practically disappeared. It is very rare nowadays to find parents, married
children, and grandchildren living together in the same house or in close
association. Large families and patriarchal groups were communities in which
children and adults had to learn (often by very painful means) the art of
co-operation and the need to accept responsibility for others. These admittedly
rather crude schools of community sense have now disappeared.
New
methods of transport have profoundly modified the life in the village and small
town. Up to only a generation ago most villages were to a great extent
self-sufficing communities. Every trade was represented by its local
technician; the local produce was consumed or exchanged in the neighborhood;
the inhabitants worked on the spot. If they desired instruction or
entertainment or religion, they had to mobilize the local talent and produce it
themselves. Today all this is changed. Thanks to improved transport, the
village is now closely bound up with the rest of the economic world. Supplies
and technical services are obtained from a distance. Large numbers of the
inhabitants go out to work in factories and offices in far-off cities. Music
and the drama are provided, not by local talent, but over the ether and in the
picture theater. Once all the members of the community were always on the spot;
now, thanks to cars, motor cycles and buses the villagers are rarely in their
village. Community fun, community worship, community efforts to secure culture
have tended to decline for the simple reason that, in leisure hours, a large
part of the community's membership is always somewhere else. Nor is this all.
The older inhabitants of Middletown, as readers of the Lynds' classical study
of American small-town life will remember, complained that the internal
combustion engine had led to a decline of neighborliness. Neighbors have Fords
and Chevrolets, consequently are no longer there to be neighborly; or if by
chance they should be at home, they content themselves with calling up on the
telephone. Technological progress has reduced the number of physical contacts,
and thus impoverished the spiritual relations between the members of a
community.
Centralized
professionalism has not only affected local entertainment; it had also affected
the manifestations of local charity and mutual aid. State-provided hospitals,
state-provided medical and nursing services are certainly much more efficient
than the ministrations of the neighbors. But this increased efficiency is
purchased at the price of a certain tendency on the part of neighbors to
disclaim liability for one another and throw their responsibilities entirely
upon the central authority. Under a perfectly organized system of state
socialism charity would be, not merely superfluous, but actually criminal. Good
Samaritans would be prosecuted for daring to interfere in their bungling
amateurish way with what was obviously a case for state-paid professionals.
The
last three generations have witnessed a vast increase in the size and number of
large cities. Life is more exciting and more money can be earned in the cities
than in villages and small towns. Hence the migration from country to city. In
the van of this migrating host have marched the ambitious, the talented, the
adventurous. For more than a century, there has been a tendency for the most
gifted members of small rural communities to leave home and seek their fortune
in the towns. Consequently what remains in the villages and country towns of
the industrialized countries is in the nature of a residual population,
dysgenically selected for its lack of spirit and intellectual gifts. Why is it
so hard to induce peasants and small farmers to adopt new scientific methods?
Among other reasons, because almost every exceptionally intelligent child born
into a rural family for a century past has taken the earliest opportunity of
deserting the land for the city. Community life in the country is thus
impoverished; but (and this is the important point) the community life of the
great urban centers is not correspondingly enriched. It is not enriched for the
good reason that, in growing enormous, cities have also grown chaotic. A
metropolitan "wen," as Cobbett was already calling the relatively
tiny London of his day, is no longer an organic whole, no longer exists as a
community, in whose life individuals can fruitfully participate. Men and women
rub shoulders with other men and women; but the contact is external and
mechanical. Each one of them can say, in the words of the Jolly Miller of the
song, "I care for nobody, no, not I, and nobody cares for me."
Metropolitan life is atomistic. The city, as a city, does nothing to correlate
its human particles into a pattern of responsible, communal living. What the
country loses on the swings, the city loses all over again on the roundabouts.
In
the light of this statement of the principal reasons for the recent decline of
the community and of the community sense in individuals, we can suggest certain
remedies. Schools and colleges can be transformed into organic communities and
used to offset, during a short period of the individual's career, the decay in
family and village life. (A very interesting experiment in this direction is
being made at Black Mountain College in North Carolina.) To some extent, no
doubt, the old, "natural" life of villages and small towns, the life
that the economic, technological and religious circumstances of the past
conspired to impose upon them, can be replaced by a consciously designed
synthetic product - a life of associations organized for local government, for
sport, for cultural activities and the like. Such associations already exist,
and there should be no great difficulty in opening them to larger numbers and,
at the same time, in making their activities so interesting that people will
wish to join them instead of taking the line of least resistance, as they do
now, and living unconnected, atomistic lives, passively obeying during their
working hours and passively allowing themselves to be entertained by machinery
during their hours of leisure. The existence of associations of this kind would
serve to make country life less dull and so do something to arrest the flight
toward the city. At the same time, the decentralization of industry and its
association with agriculture should make it possible for the countryman to earn
as much as the city dweller. In spite of the ease with which electric power can
now be distributed, the movement toward the decentralization of industry is not
yet a very powerful one. Great centers of population, like London and Paris,
possess an enormous power of attraction to industries. The greater the
population, the greater the market; and the greater the market, the stronger
the gravitational pull exercised upon the manufacturer. New industries
establish themselves on the outskirts of large cities and make them become
still larger. For the sake of slight increased profits, due to lower
distributing costs, the manufacturers are busily engaged in making London
chaotically large, hopelessly congested, desperately hard to enter or leave,
and vulnerable to air attacks as no other city of Europe is vulnerable. To
compel a rational and planned decentralization of industry is one of the
legitimate, the urgently necessary functions of the state.
Life
in the great city is atomistic. How shall it be given a communal pattern? How
shall the individual be incorporated in a responsible, self-governing group? In
a modern city, the problem of organizing responsible community life on a local
basis is not easily solved. Modern cities have been created and are preserved
by the labors of highly specialized technicians. The massacre of a few thousands
of engineers, administrators and doctors would be sufficient to reduce any of
the great metropolitan centers to a state of plague-stricken, starving chaos.
Accordingly, in most of its branches, the local government of a great city has
become a highly technical affair, a business of the kind that must be centrally
planned and carried out by experts. The only department in which there would
seem to be a possibility of profitably extending the existing institutions of
local self-government is the department concerned with police-work and the
observance of laws. I have read that in Japan, the cities were, and perhaps
still are, divided into wards of about a hundred inhabitants apiece. The people
in each ward accepted a measure of liability for one another and were to some
extent responsible for good behavior and the observance of law within their own
small unit. That such a system lends itself to the most monstrous abuses under
a dictatorial government is obvious. Indeed, it is reported that the Nazis have
already organized their cities in this way. But there is no governmental
institution that cannot be abused. Elected parliaments have been used as
instruments of oppression; plebiscites have served to confirm and strengthen
tyranny; courts of justice have been transformed into Star Chambers and
military tribunals. Like all the rest, the ward system may be a source of good
in a desirable context and a source of unmitigated evil in an undesirable
context. It remains in any case a device worth considering by those who aspire
to impose a communal pattern upon the atomistic, irresponsible life of modern
city dwellers. For the rest, it looks as though the townsman's main experience
of democratic institutions and responsible self-government would have to be
obtained, not in local administrations, but in the fields of industry and
economics, of religious and cultural activity, of athletics and entertainment.
In
the preceding paragraphs I have tried to answer the first of our questions and
have described the methods by which the principle of self-government can be
applied to the daily lives of ordinary men and women. Our second question
concerns the compatibility of self-government all round with the efficiency of
industry in particular and society as a whole. In Russia self-government in
industry was tried in the early years of the revolution and was abandoned in
favor of authoritarian management. Within the factory discipline is no longer
enforced by elected representatives of the Soviet or worker's committee, but by
appointees of the Communist Party. The new conception of management current in
Soviet Russia was summed up by Kaganovitch in a speech before the seventeenth
congress of the Communist Party. "Management," he said, "means
the power to distribute material things, to appoint and discharge subordinates,
in a word, to be master of the particular enterprise." This is a
definition of management to which every industrial dictator in the capitalist
countries would unhesitatingly subscribe.
By
supporters of the present Russian government it is said that the change over
from self-government to authoritarian management had to be made in the
interests of efficiency. That extremely inexperienced and ill-educated workers
should have been unable to govern themselves and keep up industrial efficiency
seems likely enough. But in Western Europe and the United States such a
situation is not likely to arise. Indeed, Dubreuil has pointed out that, as a
matter of historical fact, self-government within factories has often led to increased
efficiency. It would seem, then, that in countries where all men and women are
relatively well educated and have been accustomed for some time to the working
of democratic institutions, there is no danger that self-government will lead
to a breakdown of discipline within the factory or a decline in output. But,
like "liberty" the word "efficiency" covers a multitude of
sins. Even if it should be irrefragably demonstrated that self-government in
industry invariably led to a greater contentment and increased output, even if
it could be proved experimentally that the best features of individualism and
collectivism could be combined if the state were to co-ordinate the activities
of self-governing industries, there would still be complaints of "inefficiency."
And by their own lights, the complainers would be quite right. For to the
ruling classes, not only in the totalitarian, but also in the democratic
countries, "efficiency" means primarily "military
efficiency." Now, a society in which the principle of self-government has
been applied to the ordinary activities of all its members, is a society which,
for purely military purposes, is probably decidedly inefficient. A militarily
efficient society is one whose members have been brought up in habits of passive
obedience and at the head of which there is an individual exercising absolute
authority through a perfectly trained hierarchy of administrators. In time of
war, such a society can be manipulated as a single unit and with extraordinary
rapidity and precision. A society composed of men and women habituated to
working in self-governing groups is not a perfect war-machine. Its members may
think and have wills of their own. But soldiers must not think nor have wills.
"Theirs not to reason why; theirs but to do and die." Furthermore a
society in which authority is decentralized, a society composed of co-ordinated
but self-governing parts, cannot be manipulated so swiftly and certainly as a
totalitarian society under a dictator. Self-government all round is not
compatible with military efficiency. So long as nations persist in using war as
an instrument of policy, military efficiency will be prized above all else.
Therefore schemes for extending the principle of self-government will either
not be tried at all or, if tried, as in Russia, will be speedily abandoned.
Inevitably, we find ourselves confronted, yet once more, by the central evil of
our time, the overpowering and increasing evil of war.
I
must now try to answer our questions concerning the efficiency of a society
made up of co-ordinated self-governing units and the nature of the
co-ordinating body.
Dubreuil
has shown that even the largest industrial undertakings can be organized so as
to consist of a number of co-ordinated but self-governing groups; and he has
produced reasons for supposing that such an organization would not reduce the
efficiency of the businesses concerned and might even increase it. This
small-scale industrial democracy is theoretically compatible with any kind of
large-scale control of the industries concerned. It can be (and in certain
cases actually has been) applied to industries working under the capitalist
system; to businesses under direct state control; to co-operative enterprises;
to mixed concerns, like the Port of London Authority, which are under state
supervision, but have their own autonomous, functional management. In practice
this small-scale industrial democracy, this self-government for all, is
intrinsically most compatible with business organizations of the last two kinds
- co-operative and mixed. It is almost equally incompatible with capitalism and
state socialism. Capitalism tends to produce a multiplicity of petty dictators,
each in command of his own little business kingdom. State socialism tends to
produce a single, centralized, totalitarian dictatorship, wielding absolute
authority over all its subjects through a hierarchy of bureaucratic agents.
Co-operatives
and mixed concerns already exist and work extremely well. To increase their
numbers and to extend their scope would not seem a revolutionary act, in the
sense that it would probably not provoke the violent opposition which men feel
toward projects involving an entirely new principle. In its effects, however,
the act would be revolutionary; for it would result in a profound
modification of the existing system. This alone is a sufficient reason for
preferring these forms of ultimate industrial control to all others. The
intrinsic compatibility of the co-operative enterprise and mixed concern with
small-scale democracy and self-government all round constitutes yet another
reason for the preference. To discuss the arrangements for co-ordinating the
activities of partially autonomous co-operative and mixed concerns is not my
business in this place. For technical details, the reader is referred once
again to the literature of social and economic planning. I will confine myself
here to quoting a relevant passage from the admirable essay contributed by
Professor David Mitrany to the Yale Review in 1934. Speaking of the need for
comprehensive planning, Professor Mitrany writes that "this does not
necessarily mean more centralized government and bureaucratic administration.
Public control is just as likely to mean decentralization - as, for instance,
the taking over from a nation-wide private corporation of activities and
services which could be performed with better results by local authorities.
Planning, in fact, if it is intelligent, should allow for a great variety of
organization, and should adapt the structure and working of its parts to the
requirements of each case."
A
striking change of view on this point is evident in the paradox that the
growing demand for state action comes together with a growing distrust of the
state's efficiency. Hence, even among socialists, as may be seen from the more
recent Fabian tracts, the old idea of the nationalization of an industry under
a government department, responsible to Parliament for both policy and
management, has generally been replaced by schemes which even under public
ownership provide for autonomous functional managements. After describing the
constitution of such mixed concerns as the Central Electricity Board (set up in
England by a Conservative government) the British Broadcasting Corporation and
the London Transport Board, Professor Mitrany concludes that it is only
"by some such means that the influence both of politics and of money can
be eliminated. Radicals and conservatives now agree on the need for placing the
management of such public undertakings upon a purely functional basis, which
reduces the role of Parliament or of any other representative body to a
distant, occasional and indirect determination of general policy."
Above
these semi-autonomous "functional managers" there will have to be, it
is clear, an ultimate co-ordinating authority - a group of technicians whose
business it will be to manage the managers. What is to prevent the central
political executive from joining hands with these technical managers of
managers to become the ruling oligarchy of a totalitarian state? The answer is
that, so long as nations continue to prepare for the waging of scientific
warfare, there is nothing whatever to prevent this from happening - there is
every reason, indeed, to suppose that it will happen. In the context of
militarism, even the most intrinsically desirable changes inevitably become
distorted. In a country which is preparing for modern war, reforms intended to
result in decentralization and genuine democracy will be made to serve the
purpose of military efficiency - which means in practice that they will be used
to strengthen the position of a dictator or a ruling oligarchy.
Where
the international context is militaristic, dictators will use the necessity for
"defense" as their excuse for seizing absolute power. But even where
there is no threat of war, the temptation to abuse a position of authority will
always be strong. How shall our hypothetical managers of managers and the
members of the central political executive be delivered from this evil? Ambition
may be checked, but cannot be suppressed by any kind of legal machinery. If it
is to be scotched, it must be scotched at the source, by education in the
widest sense of the word. In our societies men are paranoiacally ambitious,
because paranoiac ambition is admired as a virtue and successful climbers are
adored as though they were gods. More books have been written about Napoleon
than about any other human being. The fact is deeply and alarmingly
significant. What must be the day-dreams of people for whom the world's most
agile social climber and ablest bandit is the hero they most desire to hear
about? Duces and Fuehrers will cease to plague the world only when the majority
of its inhabitants regard such adventurers with the same disgust as they now bestow
on swindlers and pimps. So long as men worship the Caesars and Napoleons,
Caesars and Napoleons will duly rise and make them miserable. The proper
attitude toward the "hero" is not Carlyle's, but Bacon's. "He
doth like the ape," wrote Bacon of the ambitious tyrant, "he doth
like the ape that, the higher he clymbes, the more he shewes his ars." The
hero's qualities are brilliant; but so is the mandril's rump. When all concur
in the great Lord Chancellor's judgment of Fuehrers, there will be no more
Fuehrers to judge. Meanwhile we must content ourselves by putting merely legal
and administrative obstacles in the way of the ambitious. They are a great deal
better than nothing; but they can never be completely effective.
(From Ends and Means)
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.