History of Scientific Thought
Although instances of scientific progress have
been documented over many centuries, the terms 'science,' 'scientists,' and the 'scientific method' were coined
only in the 19th century. Prior to this
time, science was viewed as a part of philosophy, and coexisted with other
branches of philosophy such as logic, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics,
although the boundaries between some of these branches were blurred.
In the earliest days of human inquiry,
knowledge was usually recognized in terms of theological precepts based on
faith. This was challenged by Greek philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, and
Socrates during the 3rd century BC, who suggested that the
fundamental nature of being and the world can be understood more accurately
through a process of systematic logical reasoning called rationalism. In
particular, Aristotle's classic work Metaphysics (literally
meaning 'beyond physical [existence]') separated theology (the
study of Gods) from ontology
(the study of being and existence) and universal science (the study of first principles, upon which logic is based). Rationalism (not to be confused with 'rationality') views reason as the source of knowledge or justification, and suggests that the criterion of truth is not sensory but rather intellectual and deductive, often derived from a set of first principles or axioms (such as Aristotle's 'law of non-contradiction').
The next major shift in scientific thought
occurred during the 16th century, when British philosopher
Francis Bacon (1561-1626) suggested that knowledge can only be derived from
observations in the real world. Based on this premise, Bacon emphasized
knowledge acquisition as an empirical activity (rather than as a reasoning
activity), and developed empiricism as an influential branch
of philosophy. Bacon's works led to the popularization of inductive
methods of scientific inquiry, the development of the 'scientific method'
(originally called the 'Baconian method'), consisting of systematic
observation, measurement, and experimentation, and may have even sowed the
seeds of atheism or the rejection of theological precepts as 'unobservable.'
Empiricism continued to clash with rationalism
throughout the Middle Ages, as philosophers sought the most effective way of
gaining valid knowledge. French philosopher Rene Descartes sided with the
rationalists, while British philosophers John Locke and David Hume sided with
the empiricists. Other scientists, such as Galileo Galilei and Sir Issac
Newton, attempted to fuse the two ideas into natural philosophy (the
philosophy of nature), to focus specifically on understanding nature and the
physical universe, which is considered to be the precursor of the natural
sciences. Galileo (1564-1642) was perhaps the first to state that the laws of
nature are mathematical, and contributed to the field of astronomy through an
innovative combination of experimentation and mathematics.
In the 18th century, German
philosopher Immanuel Kant sought to resolve the dispute between empiricism and
rationalism in his book Critique of Pure Reason, by arguing that
experience is purely subjective and processing them using pure reason without
first delving into the subjective nature of experiences will lead to
theoretical illusions. Kant's ideas led to the development of German
idealism, which inspired later development of interpretive techniques such
as phenomenology, hermeneutics, and critical social theory.
At about the same time, French philosopher
Auguste Comte (1798-1857), founder of the discipline of sociology, attempted to
blend rationalism and empiricism in a new doctrine called positivism.
He suggested that theory and observations have circular dependence on each
other. While theories may be created via reasoning, they are only authentic if
they can be verified through observations. The emphasis on verification started
the separation of modern science from philosophy and metaphysics and further
development of the 'scientific method' as the primary means of validating
scientific claims. Comte's ideas were expanded by Emile Durkheim in his
development of sociological positivism (positivism as a foundation for social
research) and Ludwig Wittgenstein in logical positivism.
In the early 20th century,
strong accounts of positivism were rejected by interpretive sociologists
(antipositivists) belonging to the German idealism school of thought.
Positivism was typically equated with quantitative research methods such as
experiments and surveys and without any explicit philosophical commitments,
while antipositivism employed qualitative methods such as
unstructured interviews and participant observation. Even practitioners of
positivism, such as American sociologist Paul Lazarsfield who pioneered
large-scale survey research and statistical techniques for analyzing survey
data, acknowledged potential problems of observer bias and structural
limitations in positivist inquiry. In response, antipositivists emphasized that
social actions must be studied though interpretive means based upon an
understanding the meaning and purpose that individuals attach to their personal
actions, which inspired Georg Simmel's work on symbolic interactionism, Max
Weber's work on ideal types, and Edmund Husserl's work on phenomenology.
In the mid-to-late 20th century,
both positivist and antipositivist schools of thought were subjected to
criticisms and modifications. British philosopher Sir Karl Popper suggested
that human knowledge is based not on unchallengeable, rock solid foundations,
but rather on a set of tentative conjectures that can never be proven
conclusively, but only disproven. Empirical evidence is the basis for
disproving these conjectures or 'theories.' This metatheoretical stance,
called postpositivism (or postempiricism), amends positivism
by suggesting that it is impossible to verify the truth although it is possible
to reject false beliefs, though it retains the positivist notion of an
objective truth and its emphasis on the scientific method.
Likewise, antipositivists have also been
criticized for trying only to understand society but not critiquing and
changing society for the better. The roots of this thought lie in Das Capital,
written by German philosophers Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, which critiqued capitalistic
societies as being social inequitable and inefficient, and recommended
resolving this inequity through class conflict and proletarian revolutions.
Marxism inspired social revolutions in countries such as Germany, Italy,
Russia, and China, but generally failed to accomplish the social equality that
it aspired. Critical research (also called critical theory)
propounded by Max Horkheimer and Jurgen Habermas in the 20th century,
retains similar ideas of critiquing and resolving social inequality, and adds
that people can and should consciously act to change their social and economic
circumstances, although their ability to do so is constrained by various forms
of social, cultural and political domination. Critical research attempts to
uncover and critique the restrictive and alienating conditions of the status
quo by analyzing the oppositions, conflicts and contradictions in contemporary
society, and seeks to eliminate the causes of alienation and domination (i.e.,
emancipate the oppressed class).
Related Topics
Privacy Policy, Terms and Conditions, DMCA Policy and Compliant
Copyright © 2018-2023 BrainKart.com; All Rights Reserved. Developed by Therithal info, Chennai.